(I)
Sanctions Viewed in the Light of General Ethical
Principles
(The Problems Associated with the Utilitarian Approach)
Article 41 of the United Nations Charter provides for economic and other
kinds of non-military measures for maintaining or restoring international
peace and security, without using the term sanctions to designate such
measures.1 Binding for all member states, these measures are coercive;2 they are listed in connection with the maintenance of peace in Chapter
VII of the Charter3 and have become familiar to a broad public in the wake
of the 1991 Gulf War.4 The use of economic coercion is a prior step to
military force as provided for in Art. 42ff.5 Interestingly, the Charter
grants the Security Council a monopoly over definitions in this field;
the Security Council decides on its own whether a threat to peace, a breach
of peace or an act of aggression exists.
It remains undisputed that sanctions receive legal recognition as specific
countermeasures to violations of international law and that, in the event
of such a violation, contractual obligations to the "law-breaking"
state which otherwise apply are invalidated. The problematic nature of
this issue has been thoroughly treated by the International Law Commission
of the United Nations under the heading "Legitimate application of
a sanction".6 In Art. 30 of the "Draft articles on State responsibility"
(1979), the Commission recommended a formulation of this normative priority
of sanctions in international law; the revised title of this article reads
"Countermeasures in respect of an internationally wrongful act."7
Two decisive factors influence the ethical evaluation of such measures:
(a) whether the economic sanctions are partial or comprehensive; (b) the
special economic circumstances of the country subject to these measures.
(The less economic autarky the state has, the greater the impact will be
on the living conditions of the affected citizens.8) From a legal standpoint,
sanctions which represent measures of collective security (multilateral
sanctions) in accordance with the provisions of the UN Charter are
to be distinguished from unilateral sanctions. The considerations of the
present ethical and legal evaluation are devoted primarily to comprehensive
economic sanctions in accordance with the provisions of Chapter VII of
the UN Charter.9
It is striking that the formulations of the UN Charter provide for coercive
measures only in connection with international peace and security. Human
rights are doubly disregarded in this context: (a) they are not given as
a reason for imposing coercive measures; (b) they are not taken into account
as concerns the impact of such measures upon the living conditions indeed,
upon the chances of survival of the affected people.10 In the normative
logic of the UN Charter and especially of Chapter VII peace apparently
assumes priority over human rights, as has become especially evident in
the sanctions policy of the Security Council since the end of the East-West
conflict. As regards (a), the Security Council has admittedly drawn an
indirect connection between human rights and its sanctions policy in so
far as it views grave and systematic human rights violations as threats
to international peace (for instance, in the case of the former apartheid
policy in South Africa). Often, however, it is left to the discretion of
member states led by considerations of power politics to judge whether
such violations constitute a threat to international peace. (Irrespective
of this, grave and systematic human rights offenses in a particular state
do not necessarily pose a threat to international peace and security.11)
As regards (b) the impact of sanctions upon the living conditions of
the people not even an indirect reference is drawn to human rights in
either the UN Charter or in the resolutions practice of the Security Council.12
A report to the Human Rights Commission of the United Nations publicly
criticizes this practice of the Security Council's sanctions commitee.13 It is precisely these ethical problems which prove decisive for the evaluation
of the legitimacy of the relevant measures or of the normative system of
international law which allows for such measures.
Comprehensive economic sanctions which heavily impact the life and health
of the civilian population need to be analyzed from an ethical standpoint
before a normative evaluation of the current practice in international
law can be undertaken. Indeed, comprehensive economic sanctions seem to
be the "classical" instruments for inducing submission in the
power politics of the so-called "New World Order"14
and instruments
whose permissibility must be critically examined from the standpoint of
ethics as well as of international law. It does not of necessity follow
that a measure praised as the panacea of power politics fulfills the requirements
placed on a legitimate international order.
In the first place, coercive measures like economic sanctions represent
a form of collective punishment15 and thus do not comply with the ethical
principle of individual responsibility, i. e. with the ability to attribute
behaviour to an individual. The punishment of people not responsible for
political decisions is most akin to a terrorist measure; the aim of such
a measure is to influence the government's course of action by deliberately
assaulting the civilian population.16 Purposefully injuring the innocent
is, however, an immoral act per se, one which cannot be justified by any
construction of utilitarian ethics. In accordance with the conception of
Thomas Aquinas, inquiring into the intention behind a particular decision
is of decisive value for an ethical evaluation.17 In the present context,
several conditions govern the moral permissibility of acts in which a morally
questionable bad upshot is foreseen: (a) the intended final end must be
good, (b) the intended means to it must be morally acceptable; (c) the
foreseen bad upshot must not itself be willed (that is, must not be, in
some sense, intended); and (d) the good end must be proportionate to the
bad upshot18, (that is, must be important enough to justify the bad upshot).19 The problematic nature of this utilitarian context of evaluation is plain
to view. Are those who suffer under a certain measure to be viewed sympathetically
as the victims of the pursuit of a good intention, or is their suffering
to be regarded as the deliberate component of a strategy? This debate seems
merely to invite hypocritical casuistry. The outcome for the affected population
is one and the same.
A "superficial" difference may only be discerned by an ethics
of attitude from the viewpoint of the perpetrator. The latter appeases
his conscience with reference to the unintentional but "inevitable"
side effects. In the Anglo-Saxon tradition, the so-called "Doctrine
of Double Effect" was developed, following a distinction made by Thomas
Aquinas.20 It was designed to help clarify ethical questions that arise
when a morally good end can only be reached through inflicting harm upon
other people.21 In the concrete instance of comprehensive economic sanctions
in accordance with Chapter VII of the UN Charter, the moral good that is
aspired is the maintenance or restoration of international peace; the
wrong that is thereby effected is the suffering of the civilian population
(including sickness and death as results of the mass suffering that accompanies
the breakdown in the distribution of essential commodities). According
to Quinn's ethical analysis, it is necessary to take into account the relation
which the aspired goal has to the foreseen wrong that results from it.22
In this context, Quinn refers to the difference between "terror bombing"
and "strategic" bombing in war: in the first instance, the suffering
of the civilian population is deliberately intended; in the second, the
possibility that the population will suffer is merely tolerated. In the
first instance, harm is directly inflicted, in the second case indirectly.
(In accordance with the currently valid rules of international humanitarian
law, which we will later examine more closely, terror bombings are strictly
prohibited, for the civilian population is never allowed to be the direct
target in a military conflict.) Economic sanctions, however, are in line
with the first case mentioned above: harm is directly and deliberately
inflicted so as to force the government to alter its course of action.
Comprehensive economic sanctions, then
continuing with the comparison
above have the ethical quality of terror bombings: the civilian population
is explicitly taken hostage in the framework of a security strategy of
power politics. It is self-evident that this kind of political instrumentalization
of the human being as the citizen of a community that is a subject in
international law is not compatible with his status as an autonomous
subject, i.e. with human dignity.23 People have a natural right not to
be sacrificed for a strategic purpose over whose formulation and realization
they exercise no influence. As Quinn says, "They have a right not
to be pressed, in apparent violation of their prior rights, into the service
of other people's purposes."24 In the area of ethics, the so-called
"Doctrine of Double Effect" secures every person's right to veto
"a certain kind of attempt to make the world a better place at his
expense."25 It attacks the purely utilitarian approach (the
maximization of usefulness) which, in the case of sanctions, could sacrifice the
health and prosperity of a whole people for the sake of the external political
purposes of member states in the Security Council or of another state coalition.
(This could be clarified case by case in such measures as the sanctions placed
against Iraq, Former Yugoslavia, Haiti,
etc.)
The sacrifice of a whole people for the sake of the strategic interests
of a superpower or of a coalition of states (as may be formed within the
Security Council) would appear to be in no way ethically justifiable.26 Assertions to this effect have already been made in connection with the
sanctions against South Africa: if there are no general criteria for morally
evaluating a particular political strategy, then those who have to bear
the primary costs of measures such as sanctions should be able to decide
whether they are to be imposed.27 The general ethical principle guiding
the use of sanctions should thus be that consideration be taken of the
affected population in the formulation of such measures. Precisely this
principle, however, is excluded by the nature of the coercive measures
in accordance with Chapter VII of the UN Charter. As American authors have
illustrated in an evaluation of the sanctions policy in the wake of the
Gulf War, economic sanctions cause the civilian population to be held hostage
in its own country.28 Measures such as those which explicitly intend to
harm the population are to be judged as amoral,29 for "one cannot
intentionally cripple an economy without intentionally affecting the people
whose working and consuming lives are partially constitutive of that economy."30
(II)
Sanctions Policy within the Normative System
of Modern International Law
When we view sanctions from the standpoint of moral philosophy, we must
of necessity inquire into their legitimacy within international law, especially
since the current doctrine of international law presupposes that human rights
constitute the jus cogens of general international law.31 (As above, we
will be limiting ourselves here to considering the problem posed by comprehensive
economic sanctions both unilateral and multilateral since specific
sanctions, like those placed on military goods, do not affect the fundamental
rights of the citizens as gravely.) The measures of the UN Security Council
are also obliged to comply with human rights.32 As we have discussed elsewhere,
human rights form the foundation of validity not only for every state's
internal legal system but also for international law.33 Despite the normative
connection between human rights and international law, a remarkable disparity
nevertheless remains between the rules of modern international law conforming
with human rights (such as the ban on the use of force in international
relations in connection with the abolishing of the traditional jus ad bellum)
and relics of old international law motivated by the principles of power
and national interest. The latter manifest themselves not only in the right
to veto exercised by the permanent members of the Security Council; they
additionally assert themselves in the provision regarding comprehensive
economic sanctions in accordance with Art. 41 of the Charter. The "complete
interruption of economic relations" which this article mentions without
any restrictive clause is fully in line with the tradition of medieval
military sieges, i.e. the starvation of the civilian population in the
interest of the respective power.34 The Security Council can impose such
sanctions in the event, for instance, of a threat to international peace.
The existence of such a threat is determined by the Council itself, resulting
in the problem of the arbitrariness of an interpretation motivated by mere
power politics.35 In accordance with the formulations of Art. 41, the Security
Council is in no way restricted in its power to impose sanctions; it need
not justify form and extent of the sanctions.36 The Charter's phrasing
in this context includes no reference to human rights considerations, i.e.
to the protection of the civilian population. Indeed, comprehensive sanctions
specifically target the latter.
The resolutions practice of the Security Council until now shows that
as a last resort and when in particular the interests of the permanent
members so dictate the Council is not beyond concocting a supposed threat
to international peace so as to plausibly impose measures of intervention.
(The sanctions against Haiti are a clear case in point: the USA saw to
it that the problems of democracy and human rights in the country's interior
were declared a threat to international peace.) Sanctions are used increasingly
by the Security Council as a means to discipline "unruly" regimes
(or those viewed as such by the USA). De facto, however, they share the
nature of collective punishment for the actions of the regime are attributed
to the whole population and above all are viewed in this manner by the
population in question. Economic sanctions prove counterproductive to this
extent with regard to the proclaimed goal (and in accordance with the Charter
the sole permissible one) of maintaining or restoring peace. Through such
sanctions, the resentment of the population is often awakened, for the
latter feels unrightfully persecuted. This resentment can easily give way
to new conflicts. Measures such as those taken against Iraq several years
after the end of the Kuwait occupation betray an underlying intent of
punishment and revenge, regardless of the proclaimed purpose of the resolutions.
In addition, a pronounced sense of injustice is awakened in the population
of the affected countries in the face of the selective imposition of sanctions.
Whereas in one case the occupation of foreign territory is ignored for
decades by the Security Council, the same behaviour in another case is
punished even years after the occupation has ended. Whereas in one case
the most grave human rights offenses and a systematic violation of the
basic rules of democracy are not regarded as a threat to international
peace (there are innumerable examples to support this claim), in another
case (for example, the invalidation of election results), not merely economic
but also military measures of intervention are weighed. The interests of
the permanent members of the Security Council, involved as they are in
power politics, determine the respective measures. One need not wonder
that such a "policy of double standards" the unofficial credo
of the "New World Order" produces a sense of injustice within
the states subject to it, especially as the fate of the present and future
generations are decisively marked by the measures which the Security Council
can impose.
In this context, the philosophically-minded person takes note of how
the conventional doctrine of international law makes power politics particularly
taboo. In the Western world, hardly a single expert on international law
has seriously dealt with the problematic nature of the human rights offenses
caused by the sanctions policy of the Security Council.37 It is the task
of legal philosophy to break the taboo placed on power politics by the
doctrine of international law and to expose the inconsistencies in the
normative logic of the current practice of international law in every instance
where such inconsistencies are willfully overseen due to the interests
of states acting according to the rules of power politics.38 This is especially
the case as concerns the whole sphere of collective security, which has
become the prized playground for the advocates of the "New World Order".
"Human rights" and "democracy" are the slogans of their
various ideological legitimizations. There is a peculiar contradiction
in the current sanctions policy of the United Nations, albeit one that
can be explained through the interests of power politics: whereas a violation
of human rights can constitute a ground for imposing sanctions (a threat
to international peace is asserted)39, detrimental effects upon human rights
as a result of the imposition of sanctions are ignored. On the one hand,
the doctrine of "humanitarian intervention" is celebrated as
a significant achievement of modern international law;40 on the other hand,
amidst the euphoria over the supposed re-strengthening of the United Nations
as an instrument of collective security, a rigorous sanctions policy is
permitted, one which de facto invalidates the fundamental human rights
of the affected population. This contradiction, arising from the use (or
abuse) of international law in power politics, practically forces the theoretician
to reflect anew on human rights as the foundation of international law.
Even if the opposite impression is made by the formulations of the UN
Charter and the resolutions policy of the Security Council, human rights
nevertheless constitute the normative foundation of every legal system,
and hence of international law as well. International peace should also
be defined as a norm from the standpoint of human rights, because a state
of war threatens or negates the fundamental human rights (including the
right to life). The General Assembly of the United Nations has also explicitly
stated this in its Declaration on the Right of Peoples to Peace.41 As with
democracy,42 peace should be defined as a function of human rights;43 it
is not an end in itself, independent of the individual's right to self-realization.
Similarly, a hierarchical order exists within human rights. Within this
order, the right to life assumes primary importance. Rights such as those
to health, peace and development can be derived from the right to life.44
These fundamental human rights, which are also fundamental economic and
social rights, are the precondition for the validity of fundamental rights
and freedoms in the classical European sense (civil and political rights).45 The former may hence not be sacrificed for the sake of the latter. This
is precisely what occurs, however, when the Security Council imposes comprehensive
sanctions for the (pretended) sake of defending human rights or democracy
in certain countries ("selected" by the USA as for instance,
Iraq and Haiti). In order to secure the population's political rights,
measures are introduced which violate this population's fundamental economic
and social rights. This normative contradiction does not further trouble
the Security Council, whose real intent is to test the strength of the
regime in question by taking the population hostage. The talk of human
rights or the maintenance of peace serves merely to veil the true motives
of power politics, regardless of whether these be the attempt to overthrow
the regime of the country in question (which international law prohibits)
or the altering of the regime's policy.
Due to the absence of explicit provisos in the UN Charter with regard
to human rights,46 and in view of the consequences of the comprehensive
sanctions policy described above, a general interpretation of the Charter's
provisions must be undertaken from the standpoint of international law.
Such an interpretation is especially called for in light of the fact that
the Charter's norms do not lie beyond the bounds of international law or
stand above the comprehensive normative system of international law. On
the one hand, we must inquire into the provisions in Art. 41 of the Charter
as well as into the measures of implementation and the practice of the
Sanctions Committee of the Security Council (1) in view of their compatibility
not only with the Charter's human rights goals, but more importantly with
the jus cogens of general international law. On the other hand (2), we
must analyze the sanctions policy with regard to specific instruments of
international law, such as conventions and treaties. Finally (3),
we must
apply by analogy the generally recognized principles of international humanitarian
law to the area of sanctions; our central concerns here are the unity and
consistency of the normative system in international law, without which
the sanctions policy would lose its legitimacy. (The incompatibilities
to be analyzed under the second point are valid for the imposition of sanctions
in general; in particular, they are valid for the unilateral sanctions
policy of the USA, which seems to consider this instrument to be a legitimate
means of foreign policy. These incompatibilities are only partially valid
for measures in the area of collective security, i.e. sanctions imposed
by the Security Council, as most of the conventions and declarations we
will cite contain provisos with regard to the UN Charter.) On the whole,
the standpoint of moral philosophy retains its relevance even in this legal
context; the status of the human being as subject along with the fundamental
rights he or she thus possesses constitutes our primary concern, one at
the heart of every ethical question.
All three sections of our analysis are founded on the principle that
the legitimacy of an international legal system is provided only when (a)
the central principles of human rights are respected, i.e. when the respective
normative provisions are formulated with regard to the universal validity
of human rights, and (b) when the same legal principles are valid everywhere.
This would prohibit the selectivity of power politics in the application
of norms contrary to the current "policy of double standards"
exercised by the Security Council.
If one accepts the fact that comprehensive sanctions negate or gravely
encroach upon the rights to life, health, etc. of the affected population
(the concrete economic factors of the country must be weighed in this context),
then the general provisions of Art. 41 of the UN Charter need to be interpreted
with regard to the entire normative system of international law, and restrictions
must accordingly be placed on the Security Council's margin of discretion.
(1) Concerning the Compatibility of Sanctions with
Human Rights as the jus cogens of General International Law
Sanctions which invalidate the fundamental economic and social rights
of the population (and in many cases even the right to life) are in view
of human rights as the jus cogens of international law47
impermissible.48
Not even the powers in accordance with Chapter VII of the UN Charter entitle
the Security Council to take measures of this sort. The Council must, in
fact, in accordance with Art. 24 (2) of the Charter, comply with the Purposes
and Principles of the United Nations when discharging its duties. One of
the United Nations' foremost aims, stated explicitly in Art. 1 (3),49 is that of promoting respect for human rights and fundamental freedoms
"for all without distinction".50 Thus, an "internal"
conflict appears to arise between the rules and principles on which the
Security Council's actions are based.
Even this body, then, does not stand above the law; the legitimacy of
its resolutions is founded on the universally binding norms of international
law.51 The problematic tendency of the Security Council to place itself
above the law must be decisively countered. Not even the special responsibility
its members have for the maintenance of international peace (Art. 24 [1]
of the Charter) gives rise to an absolutist right of this kind. Under the
auspices of the "New World Order", the verifiable abuse of power
which this body has been guilty of since the end of the East-West conflict
has been increasingly made taboo. This development is unfortunately abetted
by such "supreme organs" of the United Nations as the International
Court of Justice, which indirectly recognized the Security Council's legal
primacy in an Order relating to the sanctions on Libya.52 From the perspective
of legal philosophy, one cannot accept this Order of the World Court, dictated
as it is by power politics; this would merely grant recognition within
international law to the principle of power politics as expressed in
the dictum of the "normative power of the factual" and thereby
undermine any legal security with respect to the future validity of international
treaties and conventions.
From our point of view, we are forced to conclude the following by analogy
as regards the legal evaluation of resolutions adopted by the Security Council: just as the disregard of
jus cogens in the process of their adoption
invalidates international treaties, so should those resolutions adopted
by the Security Council and standing contrary to the ius cogens of international
law also be nullified. The binding norms in question are those of general
international law in accordance with the Vienna Convention on the Law of
Treaties of May 23, 1969, which confirms these as "accepted and recognized
by the international community of states as a whole as a norm from which
no derogation is permitted" (Art. 53).53 This is precisely the case
with the supreme principles of human rights.
(2) Sanctions Policy with Regard to International
Conventions
The comprehensive sanctions policy outlined above furthermore runs counter
to many international agreements and conventions, of which only a limited
number of examples can be cited in this evaluation.54 (As with the declaration
of human rights and the two International Covenants on Civil and Political
Rights and on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, the respective conventions
are surprisingly only applicable to a limited extent to the sanctions
policy of the Security Council. This clearly documents the fact that, in
the framework of the United Nations due to the circumstances of power
politics no priority is accorded to human rights, the ius cogens of international
law, a fact which we will demonstrate. From the perspective of the theory
of international law we propose, provisos in the specific conventions55 are highly problematic.56) To be considered in this regard are the provisions
set out in § 25 (1) of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948)57
and in § 11 (1) of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural
Rights (in effect since 1976).58 With reference to comprehensive sanctions
(as in the case of the oil and economic embargo against Iraq), §
1 (2) of the International Covenant is especially relevant: "In no case may
a people be deprived of its own means of subsistence." International
law, then, clearly permits no derogation from these provisions under any
circumstances.59 These guarantees for human rights are specifically upheld
in Art. 1 of the Universal Declaration on the Eradication of Hunger and
Malnutrition (1974) by the World Food Conference.60
The sanctions policy described above is furthermore contrary to the
principles of the United Nations Declaration on Principles of International
Law concerning Friendly Relations and Co-operation among States in accordance
with the Charter of the United Nations (General Assembly Resolution 2625
[XXV] of October 24, 1970). With regard to the fundamental principle of
non-intervention, the Declaration stipulates among other things that "No
State may use or encourage the use of economic, political or any other
type of measures to coerce another State in order to obtain from it the
subordination of the exercise of its sovereign rights and to secure from
it advantages of any kind."61 That which the individual state is expressly
prohibited from practicing is, in the name of "collective security",
granted to the respective group of states in the Security Council. This
is the case despite the fact that the resolutions often serve the interests
of the strongest member country and that the sanctions are de facto imposed
with the intention of destabilizing the internal politics of a country.
In a later paragraph, the declaration therefore expressly negates the validity
of its own provisions with regard to the measures authorized in accordance
with Chapter VII of the Charter.62 This proviso empties the declaration's
respective provisions of any content whatsoever; it does, however, shed
light on the true intention, one which is motivated by power politics:
to uphold the privileges of the Security Council. The provisions regarded
as fundamental for the peaceful coexistence of states are all inapplicable
to the Security Council. It is obvious that the permanent members profit
the most from such exemptions.
A rigorous sanctions regime has been and in some cases continues to
be practiced against Iraq, Serbia and Haiti by the Security Council;
this policy also manifests itself in the unilateral US sanctions against
Cuba. Such a policy in effect hinders the affected governments in fulfilling
their duties in accordance with the Charter of Economic Rights and Duties
of States (Resolution 3281 [XXIX] of the United Nations General Assembly
of December 12, 1974).
A sanctions policy of this kind runs especially counter to
Art. 7 of this charter, which details the responsibility of each state towards promoting
the economic and social development of its citizens.63 Art. 32 authoritatively
formulates the prohibition on the use of economic measures "to coerce
another state in order to obtain from it the subordination of the exercise
of its sovereign rights." (This rule was already included in the 1970
Declaration.) But here, too, power politics have stipulated a proviso (in
Art. 33): no provision of the Charter should be construed as "impairing
or derogating from the provisions of the charter of the United Nations."
In a separate resolution, the United Nations Conference on Trade and
Development condemned the application of economic coercion, especially
when the latter is used against developing countries; it furthermore referred
to the fact that such measures "do not help to create the climate
of peace needed for development." In Resolution 152 (VI) of July 2,
1983, entitled Rejection of Coercive Economic Measures, the conference
stipulated that "all developed countries shall refrain from applying
trade restrictions, blockades, embargoes and other economic sanctions incompatible
with the provisions of the Charter of the United Nations ... against developing
countries as a form of political coercion which affects their economic,
political and social development." (This resolution and those described
below are especially pertinent as concerns the United States, which have
made comprehensive, unilateral sanctions one of their foremost foreign
policy instruments in their efforts against countries which oppose the hegemonial interests of the USA.)64 Without a doubt, the collective actions
of the "developed" countries under the leadership of the USA
against Iraq, Libya and Haiti, and especially the unilateral sanctions
imposed by the USA against Cuba, are contrary to the spirit of this resolution.
In all of these cases, a threat to international peace, human rights or
democracy has been concocted; what is really meant is the refusal of the
state in question to subject itself to Western hegemonic strategies. "Human
rights", "rule of law" and "restoration of democracy"
merely serve as pretexts for unilateral measures of the USA with cover
generally provided by multilateral resolutions which aim at destabilizing
the regime in question or replacing it with one which bears the US seal
of approval.
The General Assembly has repeatedly condemned economic coercion as a
means of achieving political goals, most sharply in Resolution 210 (XLVI)
of December 20, 1991, entitled "Economic Measures as a Means of Political
and Economic Coercion against Developing Countries". Point 3 of this
resolution's catalogue of measures requires the industrial nations to reject
the use of their superior position as a means of applying economic pressure
"with the purpose of inducing changes in the economic, political,
commercial and social policies of other countries." This repeated
condemnation of such sanctions measures by bodies which when compared
with the Security Council enjoy a more democratic legitimization reveals
one possible reason why the USA refrain from the exclusive imposition of
unilateral sanctions and instead increasingly prefer to seek the Security
Council's cover (which, in the shifted constellation of world politics,
is also easier to come by). This endows them with a kind of legal immunity
for their power politics, an immunity which they need so as to deflate
the argument that such measures violate international law. The advocates
of comprehensive economic sanctions ("punitive sanctions") will
only succeed with a line of argument which upholds the primacy of the Security
Council if the doctrine of a ius cogens with principles binding upon all
organs of the United Nations is abandoned and if the Security Council is
placed above, i.e. beyond the bounds of the law. This would, however, be
tantamount to an "anarchy of sovereignty", the beneficiaries
of which would be the member states equipped with the right to veto, and
would carry the idea of an "international rule of law" ad absurdum.
The resolutions practice of the Security Council since the end of the East-West
conflict has greatly fostered this kind of development.65
By explicitly demanding an exemption with regard to measures in accordance
with Art. 41 of the UN Charter, a group of United Nations experts for
the benefit of power politics relativized the various declarations and
resolutions which have been passed since the Declaration of 1970 and which
condemn measures of economic coercion.66 This indirectly confirms the full
awareness within the United Nations of the problematic nature of the above-mentioned
measures in terms of international law, and in particular of the consistency
of the normative system as such.
For an evaluation of the economic measures of coercion from the standpoint
of international law, the Declaration on the Right to Development (Resolution
of the General Assembly [XLI] of December 4, 1986) is especially important.
Art 1., Par. 1 of the Declaration formulates an inalienable individual
and collective human right to development. This right runs counter to coercive
economic measures which, as practice proves, often lead to mass suffering.
According to this article, "The right to development is an inalienable
human right by virtue of which every human person and all peoples are entitled
to participate in, contribute to, and enjoy economic, social, cultural
and political development, in which all human rights and fundamental freedoms
can be fully realized."
After all that we have said up to this point, it should not surprise
us that this Declaration, too under Art. 9, Par. 2 formulates the usual
proviso ("Nothing in the present Declaration shall be construed as
being contrary to the Purposes and Principles of the United Nations ...");
the reference to these purposes of the United Nations, however, remains
in this instance rather vague, as it does not explicitly cite the Charter,
not to mention individual provisions therein. All of these exemptions are
contrary to human rights, the ius cogens of international law. In this
connection, one may refer to Art. 60 (5) of the Vienna Convention on the
Law of Treaties. According to this article, provisions which are contained
in treaties of a humanitarian nature and which relate to the protection
of the human person may not be invalidated on the basis of other circumstances.67 This would mean that the provisos contained in the respective conventions
completely lose their relevance in regard to the specific humanitarian
norms contained in the convention.68
The World Conference on Human Rights of the United Nations, in Par.
10 of its final document "Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action"
of June 25, 1993, also reasserted the right to development as a "universal
and inalienable right and an integral part of fundamental human rights."
Art. 14 of the Declaration specifically states that poverty inhibits the
full realization of human rights.69 Precisely this situation, however,
has been and continues to be created in many countries by the Security
Council through its policy of economic sanctions. Even the Vienna Declaration
does not omit the usual proviso when, in Art. 7, it stipulates that the
processes of promoting and protecting human rights should be conducted
in conformity with the Purposes and Principles of the UN Charter.
The most precise thematization to date (in the framework of the United
Nations) of the problematic nature of the sanctions with regard to human
rights problems has been undertaken by the UN Commission on Human Rights
in its resolution of March 4, 1994. Art. 2 expressly maintains that coercive
economic measures prevent the full realization of human rights, with special
reference to children, women and the elderly.70 Directing our attention
to the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, the resolution calls on all
states to forbear such practices. It above all refers to (in Art. 3) "the
right of everyone to a standard of living adequate for their health and
well-being, including food and medical care, housing and the necessary
social services". Art. 4 of the resolution explicitly lists restrictions
on trade, blockades, embargoes and the freezing of assets as coercive measures
constituting human rights offenses; Art. 5 expressly stipulates that essential
goods such as food and medicines may not be used as means of exerting political
pressure. It is not necessary to further elaborate on the fact that, in
substance, the circumstances described in the resolution match those of
multilateral sanctions imposed by the Security Council (in the framework
of measures of collective security).71 In order, however, to avoid a conflict
with the UN Charter, the Human Rights Commission expressly directed its
resolution, on a formal level, at unilateral coercive measures ("Human
Rights and Unilateral Coercive Measures") despite the fact that the
effects of multilateral sanctions upon human rights are far graver (because
they naturally "hit home" better). This reveals once more the
normative rift in the conscience of the United Nations organs; exempting
measures of collective security from the validity of human rights is symptomatic
of this rift. Granted, a political conflict in the framework of the United
Nations procedures and the United Nations power structures is thus avoided;
the contradiction on the normative level, however, remains, as far as concerns
the status of human rights as the ius cogens, i.e. the foundation of validity,
of international law. In actuality, the validity of human rights is made
dependent on provisions of international law in the UN Charter. But it
is precisely through these provisions that the rights demanded by the Human
Rights Commission can be invalidated in the course of collective measures
determined by power politics. Not even through reference to the priority
of peace as the guarantee of the fundamental right to life can this
normative circulus vitiosus be conjured away.
(3) Sanctions Policy and International Humanitarian
Law
For the legal evaluation of coercive economic measures imposed by the
Security Council, generally recognized provisions of international humanitarian
law72 can be especially useful. Because measures of this kind do not constitute,
from the standpoint of international law, acts of war (even though that
is what they de facto are), the laws of war in a strict sense do not apply
to them. The provisions of the Geneva Convention Relative to the Protection
of Civilian Persons in Time of War (of August 12, 1949) are, however, valid,
for they may also be applied with respect to conflicts not expressly declared
as war. Thus "the humanitarian restriction also exists for coercive
measures in accordance with Chapter VII of the Charter."73 Par. 1
of Art. 54 of the First Additional Protocol to the Geneva Conventions is
especially significant for an evaluation of comprehensive coercive economic
measures: "Starvation of civilians as a method of warfare is prohibited."74 This provision is also relevant as regards the continuation of comprehensive
sanctions against Iraq, a large portion of whose economic infrastructure
was destroyed in the course of belligerent activities based on Chapter
VII of the UN Charter75 (and clearly contrary to Art. 54, Par. 2 of the
first Additional Protocol).76
Furthermore, the provisions of Art. 48 and 49 of the First Additional
Protocol are by analogy applicable to economic sanctions (which often
serve as the first step towards or go hand in hand with coercive military
measures). In accordance with these provisions, the protection of the civilian
population calls for the latter to be distinguished in all circumstances
from the combatants.77 What applies to a military situation must apply
all the more to the implementation of coercive economic measures, for otherwise
the conduct of war would satisfy higher criteria of justice or human rights
than non-military measures. Comprehensive economic sanctions, however in contrast to partial sanctions
do not by their very nature allow for
a differentiation between the "civilian population" and the government
(or specific governmental institutions) whose policies are to be influenced
through the sanctions. Comprehensive sanctions make the civilian population
the hostage of the Security Council, of the state, or of the group of states
implementing the coercive measures. Former American Attorney-General Ramsey
Clark has fervently drawn attention to this inconsistency between the provisions
of humanitarian international law and actual United Nations practice in
the realm of economic measures based on Chapter VII of the Charter: "If
law prohibits even minimal assault on civilians in time of war, when a
government will not surrender, can it permit the assault of an entire nation
when its government will not submit, striking the poorest and weakest hardest
and killing the most fragile?"78 It is astonishing to the legal philosopher
that the sanctions policy is not measured against the normative rules of
international humanitarian law despite the fact that this policy is de
facto constitutive of a war strategy, i.e. this policy amounts to a strategy
to escalate the use of force (even though this force, if implemented under
Chapter VII of the UN Charter, is not declared as "war" in terms
of international law). As shown by the practice of the Sanctions Committee
of the Security Council especially in its handling of the Iraq sanctions
since 1990, there are no "humanitarian" scruples, despite the
fact that numerous reports (including those of representatives dispatched
by the United Nations) document in detail the catastrophic situation brought
on by the continuation of the sanctions after the war.79
The so-called Martens Clause evokes the general humanitarian principles
to which the Security Council is also bound by virtue of ius cogens during
the implementation of its sanctions policy. This rule was first formulated
in the Preamble to the Second Hague Convention of 1899 and was restated
in the Preamble to the Fourth Hague Convention of 1907. This provision
was decisive for the development of international law. It stipulates that,
in the absence of detailed provisions concerning specific areas of the
law of war, the civilian population as well as the combatants should "remain
under the protections and the rule of the principles of the law of nations,
as they result from the usages established among civilized peoples, from
the laws of humanity, and the dictates of the public conscience."80
(The Martens Clause was explicitly incorporated into the First Additional
Protocol to the Geneva Conventions of 1949.81 ) This formulation clearly
upholds human rights as the ius cogens of general international law. Thus,
the humanitarian consequences of the provisions of the UN Charter especially
those in Chapter VII must be constantly examined with regard to human
rights. This rule of interpretation resulting from the Martens Clause is
often used in the current discussion of the permissibility of weapons of
mass destruction. This interpretation applies by analogy equally to all
coercive measures which badly harm the economy and the health of the civilian
population and pose a threat to the latter's right to life; this is precisely
the case with total blockades, which cause mass suffering and destroy the
healthcare system of the country targeted. It would be absurd and contrary
to all principles of justice if one were to apply higher humanitarian standards
to war than to so-called non-military coercive measures which, like war,
can lead to death and mass deprivation.
The lack of consideration granted to provisions of humanitarian international
law (which are by analogy applicable) cannot be justified even by reference
to the maintenance of international peace according to Art. 39 of the UN
Charter. The goal of peace does not supersede human rights; on the contrary,
peace as the goal of the UN Charter can only be defined with respect to
human rights (and especially the fundamental right to life). The restoration
or maintenance of a state of affairs which preserves the fundamental human
rights cannot be gained by negating these very human rights. On grounds
of humanity, there must be normative consistency in this particular context
of international law. Otherwise, the normative system embodied in the UN
Charter loses its legitimacy. The requirements of power politics should
not establish the criteria of interpretation guiding the application of
the provisions of Chapter VII; rather, through the analogous application
of provisions for the protection of civilians in armed conflicts, international
humanitarian law should determine such guidelines.82
(III)
Concerning Collective and Individual Responsibility
in Current International Law
Outlined above is the kind of sanctions policy which either directly
causes or acknowledges the violation of human rights and the disregard
of provisions of international humanitarian law. In light of this, one
particular question necessarily arises: the question concerning the legal
and moral responsibility of the states or community of states83 (as represented
by the Security Council) authorizing or carrying out the sanctions. The
International Progress Organization raised this question with the United
Nations Human Rights Commission in connection with the sanctions against
Iraq.84 Until now, however, the doctrine of international law has hardly,
or inadequately, dealt with the issue of responsibility; apparently the
question of "guilt" has been suppressed in collective security
measures, as the many provisos in the previously quoted conventions prove.
It seems to be common belief that these measures are above general international
law or that they invalidate every other international law, as can be expressed
by the following maxim: "Security (Council) law invalidates international
law (or the law of human rights). " Clearly, this cannot satisfy the
legal philosopher, whose concerns are the universal validity of norms and
the legitimacy of legal systems.
The considerations laid out by Jean Combacau in his work on the theory
of non-military coercive measures typify the conventional standpoint of
experts on international law on sanctions and the responsibility accompanying
them.85 Combacau completely disregards the ethical aspects of sanctions
in connection with the population of the affected country. He elaborates
on the moral aspect only in regard to people in neighboring countries who
suffer as a result of a sanctions measure. Combacau speaks of "exigence
morale" as concerns the obligation of solidarity with these victims
(among whom, however, the civilian population of the affected country is
not included).86 In connection with Art. 50 of the UN Charter, he describes
the existence of a legal obligation regarding the neighboring states affected
by the sanctions,87 without, however, going into the rights of the civilian
population directly affected. In his report on United Nations reform, "An
Agenda for Peace", UN General Secretary Boutros-Ghali also willfully
overlooks the question of liability as regards the population of the country
affected by the sanctions when he suggests improvements to reparation measures
for third countries.88 In his recent report (Supplement to an Agenda for
Peace: Position Paper of the Secretary-General on the Occasion of the Fiftieth
Anniversary of the United Nations) he addresses, for the first time, the
problematic nature of sanctions in regard to ethical questions.89
Konrad Ginther has proposed a theory concerning the responsibility of international
organizations under international law;90 however, this theory does not
help to resolve the questions of liability raised by the sanctions. He
views the United Nations Organisation as regards its status in international
law as a universal organization; Ginther thus regards the measures of the
Security Council as being, as it were, ex definitione "always in the
interest of the entire international community"91 . From this standpoint,
there is "at least theoretically" no possibility of a collision
between the individual interest of a member state (and probably "individual
rights" of that state as well) and the interests of the community
of nations as represented by the United Nations Organisation.92 This interpretation
is naturally supported by the provisions of Art. 24 (1) of the Charter.93 Ginther apparently disregards the fact that the general responsibility
of the Security Council for peace and security (as stated in this paragraph)
disguises an underlying policy of interests of the permanent members of
the Security Council. With regard to the postulated universality, Ginther
formulates a fictitious principle which can only be taken cynically by
the population whose human rights are affected by the sanctions: "the
measure adopted by the organisation in conformity with its Charter is always
to be regarded as being in the interest of the affected state."94 Ginther seems not to have considered what consequences this formulation
could have for the escalation of coercive economic measures, for the maxim
he proposes instrumentalizes the rights of the civilian population (i.e.,
their human rights) for the benefit of an abstract state; this maxim thereby
runs counter to a central area of the ius cogens of general international
law. From a formal standpoint, Ginther correctly concludes from the universal
nature of the United Nations Organisation that "the organisation alone,
to the exclusion of a subsidiary liability of the member states, is responsible
for the consequences resulting from a violation of rights by one of its
organs."95 This general statement is problematic, however, with regard
to the privileged position of the permanent members of the Security Council,
for these members can steer a resolution in a particular direction by means
of their right to veto.96 Judging from what has been said, Ginther would
probably not apply the principle of liability to the sanctions resolutions
of the Security Council, for such measures, from his standpoint, cannot eo ipso run counter to the interests of member states. In addition, current
international law provides for no mechanism for determining and requiting
a human rights violation caused by the Security Council. Neither does Ginther,
in his exhaustive considerations on international law, make reference to
the problems associated with the damage caused by a comprehensive sanctions
policy to the whole population of a country. From the standpoint of conventional
international law, the Security Council is apparently immune, due to the
philosophy or rather, ideology of "collective security";
it is not possible for the Council to violate any rights as long as it
adheres to the formal framework of the Charter's provisions. The ideology
of universality does not even allow for a substantive (material) examination
and normative evaluation of the Security Council's sanctions policy.
We are thus forced to acknowledge that the current theory of international
law completely overlooks issues of human rights and issues of liability
closely connected with the latter. This deficiency is all the more aggravated
by the fact that the sanctions policy in accordance with Chapter VII can
gravely violate the fundamental human rights of a whole generation of people.
A moral-philosophical critique of the current UN Charter is urgently called
for, one which considers the latter as it is actually interpreted by the
"superpowers" (which above all exploit the provisions of Chapter
VII). It is inexcusable that these superpowers escape their responsibility
precisely through reference to their special responsibility in accordance
with Art. 24 and the provisions of Chapter VII and that they furthermore
have their "immunity" indirectly confirmed by the International
Court of Justice, as occurred de facto in the Order on the Libya case cited
above. Despite this fact of power politics, we must assert that not only
nations defeated in war but also the organs of the United Nations due
to the universal validity of human rights have a specific duty to undertake
reparations towards every person whose rights has been affected by sanctions.
This is the case because the comprehensive economic sanctions described
above are an illegitimate instrument of collective punishment and contrary
to the ius cogens of international law; they should never have been allowed,
in this general form, to become embodied in the UN Charter.
To the extent that on the basis of human rights
the organs of the
United Nations are completely responsible for the consequences of resolutions
contrary to the ius cogens, the question concerning the applicability of
the principles of the Nürnberg Tribunal and of the Genocide Convention
can certainly be raised.97 Why should they not apply? As the delegate of
the International Progress Organization maintained in the statement presented
to the Human Rights Commission and quoted above, certain sanctions measures
of the Security Council represent grave and systematic violations of the
fundamental human rights of an entire population of a state.98
The principles of the Nürnberg War Crimes Tribunal99 have already
been discussed publicly in this connection.100 Chapter B, Point (c) mentions
"crimes against humanity" as wrongdoings to be duly punished
as crimes under international law. In accordance with the definition provided
by the Nürnberg Tribunal and adopted by the International Law Commission
of the United Nations, crimes against humanity101 encompass not only murder,
enslavement, deportation etc.; they also include "other inhuman acts
done against a civilian population, ... when such acts are done ... in
execution of or in connection with any crime against peace or any war crime."102
This definition can certainly apply to a deliberate sanctions policy though only in connection with belligerent acts in the course of which
war crimes have been committed. The definition gains relevance especially
in cases such as the case of Iraq where, following the strategic destruction
of the economic infrastructure of a whole country in the course of belligerent
acts (in violation of the Geneva Conventions), sanctions measures deny
the population the right to adequate nutrition and appropriate medical
care over an extended period of time. With reference to the sanctions imposed
against Iraq, former US Attorney-General Ramsey Clark has repeatedly and
fervently pointed out evidence of a crime against humanity in accordance
with the Nürnberg principles.103
The resulting personal criminal responsibility of the respective decision
makers of the member states of the Security Council can also be shown with
regard to the provisions of the Genocide Convention. In accordance with Art. II, the evidence of genocide is defined on the basis of acts with
the intent to destroy a national, ethnic, racial or religious group is
aspired; one means among others towards this end is "deliberately
inflicting on the group conditions of life calculated to bring about its
physical destruction in whole or in part."104 In a petition to the
United Nations, the American expert on international law, Francis Boyle,
regarded this evidence to be present in connection with the Iraq sanctions;
accordingly, in the name of the children affected most deeply by the sanctions,
he demanded legal measures against those responsible.105
In connection with recent attempts to formulate definitions in international
law, another document is relevant, namely the draft of the International
Law Commission concerning the responsibility of a state for its internationally
wrongful acts. Article 19 of the draft defines the term "international
crime" as an "internationally wrongful act which results from
the breach of a state of an international obligation so essential for the
protection of fundamental interests of the international community that
its breach is recognized as a crime by that community as a whole."106
Under Point (c), the Commission provides as an example of international
crime "a serious breach on a widespread scale of an international
obligation of essential importance for safeguarding the human being, such
as those prohibiting slavery, genocide and apartheid."107 In the context
of the Commission's codification efforts in international law, the definition
applies to the policies of individual states;108 by analogy, however, it
should be equally applicable to acts of a community of states as represented
by the Security Council, whereby (disregarding the theory formulated by Ginther) every state should be held individually accountable for its participation
in sanctions resolutions that are contrary to human rights. If evidence
of genocide as defined above is found, the individual responsibility of
the member states of the Security Council would have to be determined in
accordance with this definition of "international crime".
A specialist for United Nations reform, Erskine Childers, has drawn
attention to other legal issues. He has documented that recent sanctions
resolutions have come about with the help of economic pressure and bribery.
In his opinion, a practice of this sort, especially when perpetrated by
a permanent member of the Security Council, undermines the sovereignty
of the member states and thus gravely violates the UN Charter. A member
state suspected of such practice should be, in his eyes, held accountable
before "a court of international criminal law".109 However, there
exist as of yet no legal instruments which would allow this kind of justifiable
demand to be realized. The practice which Childers condemns is blatantly
contrary to the provisions set out in the Declaration on Principles of
International Law Concerning Friendly Relations and Co-operation among
States in accordance with the Charter of the United Nations (1970).
(IV)
Consequences from the Perspective of Legal
Philosophy:
Chances for the Further Humanitarian Development of International Law?
If we consider this list of inconsistencies and incompatibilities of
sanctions measures with regard to international law and above all as
concerns the universal validity of human rights and if we furthermore
take account of the ethical impermissibility of the sanctions policy described
above, we are left to call for the further humanitarian development of
international law, especially with respect to the rights and duties of
the Security Council. Above all, criteria should be formulated within the
framework of the United Nations (it would make most sense for the International
Court of Justice to undertake this) that would eliminate conflicts between
specific purposes and principles of the UN Charter in favor of the primacy
of human rights. The Security Council, in accordance with Art. 24 (2), should also be bound to these criteria.110 Coming to terms with the current
state of affairs would amount to recognizing the primacy of the Security
Council, not merely above the other organs of the United Nations, but also
above international law as a whole, including the ius cogens to which the
community of nations is bound. Should the principles of power politics
indeed supersede the general principles of law as the UN Charter is interpreted
in current practice the legitimacy of international law would be seriously
undermined. If the principles of power politics, as manifested in the "policy
of collective security" in accordance with Chapter VII of the Charter,
violate the ius cogens of general international law (as clearly documented
by the many provisos in the international conventions cited here), then
the talk of the universality of principles of international law loses all
meaning whatsoever.
Let us in addition consider the fact that the current sanctions practice
of the Security Council in accordance with the security doctrine of the
"New World Order" is detrimental to a comprehensive policy of
peace, for sanctions are in many cases part of a war strategy and abet
the preparations towards or the continuation of war. The affected population
can only take this as an act of aggression on the part of a coalition of
states (or war coalition, as in the case of the Gulf War) taking advantage
of the Security Council. With this consideration in mind, one is forced
to call for a modification of the UN Charter to bring about a genuine policy
of peace and human rights. If as the Security Council's current position
seems to be the restoration of a positive order of peace includes "not
merely the suspension of war activities, but more importantly the respect
for human rights,"111 then one cannot disregard the most fundamental
human rights of the entire population affected by sanctions.112 While securing
political rights and classical civil rights, one must not invalidate economic
and social rights including the right to life and health. The arbitrariness
of the Security Council's power politics must be reigned in; the Council
at present ignores its responsibility in this regard and bypasses the will
of the affected population, directing attention instead to its primary
responsibility for world peace in general. Only the principle which stipulates
the conformity of all decisions with human rights can be the foundation
of a legitimate international legal order, i.e. of the international rule
of law.113 It is especially necessary that an extra human rights clause
be added to the provisions of Art. 41 of the UN Charter so that, in the
statutory framework of the United Nations, the conformity of sanctions
measures with the requirements of human rights can be explicitly demanded
(even if our considerations from the standpoint of legal theory have shown
a collective duty of this kind as already applying to the member states
of the Security Council).114 In the current discussion of the practice
of sanctions, more radical suggestions have been made with the aim of adopting
an international convention to prohibit economic blockades.115
Regardless of how one judges the actual political chances of such proposals
for reform, it is inexcusable in view of the most recent sanctions practice
established by the Western states to continue placing taboos on the powers
of the Security Council. The relics of the old system of international
law, which was determined by the concept of power, need to be consistently
disclosed for what they are. If under the auspices of the New/ Old World
Order the provisions in the UN Charter with regard to collective security
present de facto a loophole for the old power politics, then we must consistently
demand that the use of these provisions conform with human rights. It is
inadmissible that medieval methods of siege and war tactics which include
the imposition of total blockades against countries that are (economically)
not self-sufficient are to be regarded as such are justified as measures
for the protection of world peace and human rights. The philosopher of
law, if no one else, must refrain from joining the conspiracy of silence
obviously constructed by the beneficiaries of the "New World Order."
|
Endnotes
-
Concerning the legal problem of sanctions in general, cf. Vera Gowlland-Debbas,
"Security Council Enforcement Action and Issues of State Responsibility,"
in: International and Comparative Law Quarterly, vol. 43 (1994), pp. 55-98.
Cf. also Gowlland-Debbas, Collective Responses to Illegal Acts in International
Law. United Nations Action in the Question of Southern Rhodesia. Dordrecht/
Boston/ London 1990, Chapter 6: "The Adoption of Collective Measures
within the Framework of Chapter VII," pp. 423ff. Cf. also C. Lloyd
Brown-John, Multilateral Sanctions in International Law. A Comparative
Analysis. New York/ Washington/ London 1975.
-
The coercive nature of these measures follows especially from
Art. 25
of the Charter.
-
"Action with Respect to Threats to the Peace, Breaches of the Peace,
and Acts of Aggression."
-
The International Law Commission of the United Nations has attempted
to define the concept of sanctions, which is not used in the Charter. The
Commission claims to reserve the use of this concept "for reactive
measures applied by virtue of a decision taken by an international organization
following a breach of an international obligation having serious consequences
for the international community as a whole, and in particular for certain
measures which the United Nations is empowered to adopt, under the system
established by the Charter, with a view to the maintenance of international
peace and security." (Draft articles on State responsibility: Report
of the Commission to the General Assembly on the work of its thirty-first
session, in: Yearbook of the International Law Commission, 1979, Vol. II,
Part Two, United Nations, New York 1980, p. 121.)
-
In fact, however, economic sanctions measures are maintained by the Security
Council in particular cases even after the use of military force has been
ended. This is highly problematic with regard to the formulation in Chapter
VII. Cf. point 32 of the report of the 18th Roundtable of the International
Institute of Humanitarian Law: Current Problems of International Humanitarian
Law. San Remo 1993, p. 20.
-
Yearbook of the International Law Commission, 1979, Vol. II, Part One:
Documents of the thirty-first session. United Nations, New York 1981, pp.
39ff. Concerning the power of the Security Council to impose sanctions
cf. pp. 43f.
-
"The wrongfulness of an act of a State not in conformity with an
obligation of that State towards another State is precluded if the act
constitutes a measure legitimate under international law against that other
State, in consequence of an internationally wrongful act of that other
State." (Yearbook of the International Law Commission, 1979, Vol.
II, Part Two: Report of the Commission to the General Assembly on the work
of its thirty-first session, United Nations, New York 1980, p. 93. Concerning
this power of the Security Council in this respect, cf. para. 13 of the
commentaries relating to Art. 30, p. 119.
-
If, in the course of military measures, the economic infrastructure of
a country has been impaired, economic sanctions will have a far graver
effect than if this infrastructure is intact. If the effects of sanctions
are to be adequately evaluated, one must therefore always take into account
the general framework of economic conditions of a country (with regard
to economic autarky) as well as its actual economic situation (state of
affairs). On this whole complex of questions, see now Chapter III/E of
the UN Secretary-General's Report to the Fiftieth Session of the General
Assembly: Supplement to an Agenda for Peace: Position Paper of the Secretary-General
on the Occasion of the Fiftieth Anniversary of the United Nations, Doc.
A/50/60, 3/ 1995/ 1, 3 January 1995, esp. paras. 67 and 75.
-
In the sense of the formulation in Art. 41: "complete... interruption
of economic relations."
-
Claire Palley refers unmistakably to these effects in a report for the
Commission on Human Rights of the United Nations (Sub-Commission on Prevention
of Discrimination and Protection of Minorities): "Sanctions imposed
by the Security Council have indiscriminately impacted on civilian populations"
(Implications of Humanitarian Activities for the Enjoyment of Human Rights,
Doc. E/CN.4/Sub.2/1994/39, 15 June 1994, para. 14, p. 6).
-
Cf. Lori Fisler Damrosch, "Commentary on Collective Military Intervention
to Enforce Human Rights," in: Lori Fisler Damrosch and David J. Scheffer
(eds.), Law and Force in the New International Order. Boulder/ San Francisco/
Oxford 1991, p. 217.
-
Exemptions with regard to the delivery of food and medicines cannot
be viewed as taking properly into account the humanitarian consequences
if the sanctions deny the country the financial means for procuring such
goods. In addition, they cannot be viewed as such if the Sanctions Committee
of the Security Council as has happened in recent practice administers
these exemptions so restrictively that one can only speak of a cynical
contempt of the affected population. Cf. particularly the effects of the
sanctions against Iraq according to the following sources: the reports
of the Harvard Study Team of May 1991; the Committee to Save the Children
in Iraq; the UN special envoys Martti Ahtisaari (20 March 1991);
and Sadruddin
Aga Khan (15 July1991); the UNICEF delegate Eric Hoskins (Children, War
and Sanctions [April 1993]); as well as the updated report of OSPAAAC (Madrid),
Contra los embargos y sanciones económicas, Dossier I/2: Irak. Concerning
the more general exemptions of, for instance, the former sanctions against
Rhodesia, cf. Gowlland-Debbas, Collective Responses to Illegal Acts in
International Law, op. cit., pp. 591ff.
-
"It is arguable that the Sanctions Committee does not have adequate
information to act promptly to suspend the operation of sanctions when
undue suffering is being caused by an embargo on particular commodities."
(Claire Palley, loc. cit., para. 14, p. 7)
-
Cf. especially the analysis of Chandra Muzaffar,
Human Rights and the
New World Order, Penang 1993, Chapter 6: "The New World Order: Subjugating
Iraq and Libya," pp. 60ff.
-
Cf. also the working paper "L'embargo" (Les cahiers de Nord-Sud
XXI, N. 1 [Geneva 1993], Chapter 2:"Violation des droits de l'Homme
et des peuples," p. 6): "Le caractère collectif dénature
l'application de la sanction et la rend incompatible avec le respect des droits de l'Homme."
-
According to Jeff McMahan and Robert Kim, "The Just War and the
Gulf War," in: Canadian Journal of Philosophy, vol. 23, n. 4, December
1993 p. 536.
-
"Morales autem actus recipiunt speciem secundum id quod inteditur,
non autem ab eo quod est praeter intentionem, cum sit per accidens."
(Summa theologica, II-II, qu. 64, Art. 7, vol. 3, ed. Rubers/ Billuart
et al., vol. 3, Taurini 1932, p. 379).
-
Cf. the principle of proportionality as formulated by Thomas Aquinas
in the context mentioned: "Potest tamen aliquis actus ex bona intentione
proveniens, illicitus reddi, si non sit proportionatus fini." (Summa
theologica, II-II, qu. 64, Art. 7, op. cit., p. 380.)
-
Cf. the portrayal by Warren S. Quinn, "Actions, Intentions, and
Consequences: The Doctrine of the Double Effect," in: Philosophy and
Public Affairs, vol. 11 (1989), pp. 334-351.
-
"nihil prohibet unius actus esse duos effectus, quorum alter solum
sit in intentione, alius vero sit praeter intentionem." (Summa theologica,
II-II, qu. 64, Art. 7, p. 379).
-
Cf. Warren S Quinn, "Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The
Doctrine of the Double Effect," op. cit.
-
Op. cit., p. 338.
-
Cf. the author's essay, "Democracy and Human Rights," here.
-
Op. cit., p. 350f.
-
Op. cit., p. 351.
-
The individual has a prima facie right not to be sacrificed for the
sake of the settlement of conflicts between states or in in the attempts
particular member states of the Security Council to make the world a better
place. In this context, there is no ethical defense of the worn-out dictum
that the end justifies the means.
-
According to Robert Paul Wolff in: "The moral dimensions of the
policy of anti-apartheid sanctions," in: Mark Orkin (ed.), Sanctions
against Apartheid. (Cape Town/ Johannesburg/ London 1989. p. 108.
-
Jeff McMahan/ Robert McKim, op. cit., p. 536. Concerning the morally
problematic nature of the Gulf War, cf. also David E. Decosse (ed.), But
Was It Just? Reflections on the Morality of the Persian Gulf War. New York
1992.
-
This is also the viewpoint which the Catholic Church has repeatedly
expressed. Cf. the quoted statements by the Archbishop of the Roman Curia
Alois Wagner, "Embargos treffen nur die Armen," Der Standard (Vienna),
11 March 1994, p. 5.
-
McMahan/ Kim, op. cit., p. 540.
-
In the modern theory of international law, ius cogens
in accordance
with the definition in Art. 53 of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties
of 23 May 1969 refers to the peremptory norms of general international
law. Art. 53 of the Convention states that "a peremptory norm of general
international law is a norm accepted and recognized by the international
community of states as a whole as a norm from which no derogation is permitted
and which can be modified only by a subsequent norm of general international
law having the same character." (Cf. also Alfred Verdross/ Bruno Simma,
Universelles Völkerrecht. Theorie und Praxis. Berlin [3rd ed.] 1984,
p. 331). The fundamental human rights are unanimously held to be part of
this ius cogens, which has in addition "absolute validity ... so that
it cannot be abrogated either by customary international law or by the
agreements between individual parties" (Verdross/ Simma, op. cit.,
p. 331). From our point of view, the absolute validity of the norms of
the ius cogens implies that the Charter of the United Nations, too, must
only be applied in accordance with human rights. This provides a clear
frame of reference for the Security Council with respect to the structuring
of the sanctions policy, i.e. it considerably restricts its freedom of
judgment based solely on the considerations of power politics.
-
This is stressed by Robert Charvin with reference to the sanctions policy
in his paper "L'embargo" (Les Cahiers de Nord-Sud XXI, no. 1,
Geneva 1993, p. 6): "les droits de l'Homme "ont pleine vigeur
et doivent ne pas être mises en cause par la sanction prise ... En
aucun cas, leur violation ne peut être justifée par le droit
d'exercer des sanctions". Concerning the complex legal problematic
of the sanctions, cf. also Charvin, "L'embargo," in: Nord-Sud
XXI. Droits de l'Homme Liberté, no. 5 (1994), pp. 123-132.
-
Cf. the author's "The Principles of International Law and Human
Rights," in: Hans Kφchler, Democracy and the International Rule of
Law. Propositions for an Alternative World Order. Vienna / New York: Springer, 1998, pp. 63-84.
-
McMahan/ Kim have characterized the current sanctions against Iraq in
a similar way (op. cit., p. 536).
-
Many jurists, however especially in "dissenting opinions"
in connection with rulings and opinions of the International Court of
Justice have referred to the fact that the margin of discretion of the
Security Council is not unlimited and that a threat to peace and international
security should not be allowed to be arbitrarily concocted for the sake
of other ends . Cf. Legal Consequences for States of the Continued Presence
of South Africa in Namibia [South West Africa] Notwithstanding Security
Council Resolution 276 [1970], Advisory Opinion of 21 June 1971: I.C.J.
Reports 1971, dissenting opinion of Judge Fitzmaurice, p. 294, para. 116.
In his dissenting opinion, he views it as necessary to restrict the power
of the Security Council "because of the all too great ease with which
any acutely controversial international situation can be represented as
involving a latent threat to peace and security, even where it is really
too remote genuinely to constitute one." (ibid.) The course taken
by the Security Council against Haiti is clear proof of the problematic
nature of an unlimited margin of discretion.
-
The validity of the resolutions of the Security Council in this regard
is to be seen, however, in connection with the formulation of Art. 25 of the Charter, which expressly refers to the carrying out of the decisions
by member states "in accordance with the present Charter". This
implies a restriction of the Council's power with regard to the other provisions
of the Charter. This line of argumentation was more thoroughly expanded
by Sir Gerald Fitzmaurice in the dissenting opinion cited above: I.C.J.
Reports 1971, p. 293, para. 113).
-
This deficit is especially blatant in the programmatic treatise by Theo
van Boven, the former Director of the UN Centre for Human Rights, "The
Security Council: The New Frontier," in: The Review [International
Commission of Jurists], no. 48, June 1992, pp.12-23. Cf. however Hans
Peter Gasser, "Protection of the Civilian Populations of States under
Embargo Measures [Summary of Statement]," in: Current Problems of
International Humanitarian Law [International Institute of Humanitarian
Law],
San Remo 1993, pp. 41-43. Cf. also the report of the 18th Roundtable
of the International Institute of Humanitarian Law, "The Protection
of Populations of States which are under Embargo," in: Current Problems
of International Humanitarian Law, pp. 19ff. Both reports carefully and
indirectly criticize the sanctions policy of the Security Council.
-
Cf. this accurate characterization in the publication of the International
Institute of Humanitarian Law: "... a certain inconsistency was noted
in the United Nations action: on the one hand imposing an embargo and on
the other hand developing modalities to assist the victims of such measures."
(Current Problems of International Humanitarian Law, p. 21.)
-
The concept of the threat to international peace is interpreted in a
very general sense in the tradition of the Security Council resolutions,
as Verdross/ Simma also point out (op. cit., p. 148).
-
Cf. Tom J. Farer, "An Inquiry into the Legitimacy of Humanitarian
Intervention," in: Lori Fisler Damrosch/ David J. Scheffer, op. cit.,
pp. 185-201.
-
Resolution 39/11 of 12 November 1984, para. 4: "life without war
serves as the primary international requisite ... for the full implementation
of the rights and fundamental freedoms proclaimed by the United Nations."
-
Cf. the author's essay "Democracy and Human Rights,"
in: Hans Kφchler, Democracy and the International Rule of Law, pp. 3-17.
-
Concerning the relation of human rights and peace in the system of norms
of the UN Charter, cf. the working paper of the Commission on Human Rights/
Sub-Commission on Prevention of Discrimination and Protection of Minorities,
Forty-sixth session, item 14 of the provisional agenda: International Peace
and Security as an Essential Condition for the Enjoyment of Human Rights,
above all the Right to Life: "Interrelationship between human rights
and international peace" (supplementary working paper prepared by
Mr. Murlidhar Bhandare) Doc. E/CN.4/Sub.2/1994/29, 22 June 1994, esp. para.
22.
-
Cf. Samuel S. Kim, "Global Human Rights and World Order,"
in: Falk/ Kim/ Mendlovitz (eds.), The United Nations and a Just World Order,
Boulder/ San Francisco/ Oxford 1991, pp. 370f.
-
Cf. the author's analysis in "The Principles of International Law
and Human Rights," in: Hans Kφchler, Democracy and the
International Rule of Law, pp. 63-84.
-
The purposes in Art. 1 (3) and the corresponding demands under
Art.
55 (c) can only be applied in a limited way as an "internal frame
of reference" for the evaluation of the resolutions procedure of the
Security Council. This is the case because the human rights goals seem
to be parallel to the provisions on international security in the context
of the Charter.
-
Concerning the embodiment of human rights in modern international law,
cf. the comprehensive documentation by Paul Sieghart, The International
Law of Human Rights, Oxford 1983; reprint 1992.
-
Concerning the theory of human rights as ius cogens in connection with
the problem of sanctions, cf. also Robert Charvin, "Droits de l'Homme:
une exigence de clarification," in: Nord-Sud XXI. Droits de l'Homme Liberté, no. 5 (1994), pp. 5-8. Concerning the current discussion
about this problem (in connection with the imposition of a state of emergency),
cf. also the Seventh Annual Report of the Special Rapporteur of the Commission
on Human Rights (Sub-Commission on Prevention of Discrimination and Protection
of Minorities, Forty-sixth session, item 10 [b] of the provisional agenda:
The Administration of Justice and the Human Rights of Detainees: Question
of Human Rights and States of Emergency), Doc. E/CN.4/Sub.2/1994/23, 3
June 1994, Chapter I: "Question of Inalienable or Non-derogable Rights".
-
Cf. the formulation of purposes of Art. 55(c) and the collective "pledge"
stated in Art. 56.
-
Cf. also the detailed report by Claire Palley for the Commission on
Human Rights, op. cit., para. 13ff. The author of this report accurately
states therein that measures to maintain international peace "potentially
conflict with other United Nations mandates," particularly with the
purposes laid out in Art. 1 (3), to which the promotion of human rights
belongs (para. 13, p.6).
-
The delegate of Zimbabwe has made accurate reference to this in the
Security Council debate concerning the Lockerbie dispute: "Any approach
that assumes that international law is created by majority votes in the
Security Council is bound to have far-reaching ramifications which could
cause irreparable harm to the credibility and prestige of the Organization,
with dire consequences for a stable and peaceful world order." (United
Nations, Security Council, Doc. S/PV.3063, 31 March 1992, p. 54)
-
Ruling of 14 April 1992 (1992, 14 April, General List No. 88/Case Concerning
questions of Interpretation and Application of the 1971 Montreal Convention
Arising from the Aerial Incident at Lockerbie [Libyan Arab Jamahiriya v.
United Kingdom], Request for the Indication of Provisional Measures). Cf.
particularly "Declaration of Acting President Oda", part I, with
regard to the Court's exclusive formulation of its ruling on the basis
of the resolution of the Security Council ("... I am not in agreement
with the Court's taking UN Security Council resolution 748 [1992] as its
sole ground in this matter"). Cf. also the contribution to the debate
by the delegate of Zimbabwe in the session of the Security Council on 31
March 1992, in which he appealed to the Council to recognize the legal
competence of the International Court of Justice in accordance with the
Charter and not to impose measures in accordance with Chapter VII before
the International Court has announced its ruling : "By taking the
Chapter VII route while this case is still pending before the world Court,
the Security Council is risking a major institutional crisis. Such an institutional
crisis ... would ... sap international confidence in the Security Council's
capacity to execute, in a judicious and objective manner, its mandate as
provided for in the Charter." (S/PV.3063, 31 March 1992, p. 53.)
-
Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (23 May 1969), Doc. A/CONF.39/27,
quoted from Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties with Final Act of
the Conference, Declarations and Resolutions. London 1969, p. 18.
-
The approach we have chosen here is also apparent in Claire Ralley's
report to the UN Commission on Human Rights. The report accuses the Security
Council with, however, the diplomatic caution obviously necessary in
this framework of violating the standards of human rights of the United
Nations ("flouting a United Nations standard") in connection
with its sanctions practice (Claire Palley, loc. cit., para. 13, p. 17).
-
The Charter of the United Nations has anyhow taken the necessary precautions
in Art. 103 and thus claimed the status of ius cogens for the norms which
it formulates ("In the event of a conflict between the obligations
of the Members of the United Nations under the present Charter and their
obligations under any other international agreement their obligations under
the present Charter shall prevail."). The "ius cogens of the
Charter" must nevertheless orient itself according to the ius cogens
of general international law; it may thus not conflict with the universal
validity of human rights. This was also emphasized in the report of the
18th Roundtable of the International Institute of Humanitarian Law: "Article
103 of the Charter could not be interpreted as justifying a disregard of
these principles and rules." (Current Problems of International Humanitarian
Law, op. cit., p. 20.)
-
The reservations are formulated in a more or less specific manner.
Art.
29 (3) of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights thus states that "These
rights and freedoms may in no case be exercised contrary to the purposes
and principles of the United Nations." With regard to Art. 1 (1) of the UN Charter, this could mean a "normative priority" of the
Security Council even in questions of human rights. This is above all the
case because the formulation of the Council's obligations in Art. 25 (2)
(which is binding for the Security Council) expressly refers to its powers
in accordance with Chapter VII. The identical reservation in Art. 46 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (or
Art. 24 of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights), by
contrast, refers solely to the rights protected in accordance with both
Conventions. The aim is merely to preclude a contradiction with the other
UN provisions "with respect to the matters treated in this covenant".
The situation is very different as concerns the other conventions treated
in this analysis. In these conventions, the reservations refer either explicitly
to the provisions of Chapter VII or generally to the provisions of the
UN Charter. With reference to the reservation in the Universal Declaration
of Human Rights, Torkel Opsahl accurately speaks of the impression "that
the parent organization somewhat self-righteously takes the opportunity
to claim priority for its own purposes and principles." (The Universal
Declaration of Human Rights: A Commentary, ed. by Asbjørn Eide et
al., Oslo 1992, p. 450.)
-
"Everyone has the right to a standard of living adequate for the
health and well-being of himself and his family, including food, ... medical
care" etc.
-
As regards the specific situation of children,
Art. 6 of the Convention
on the Rights of the Child is relevant.
-
In this context, we need not make further mention of the fundamental
right to life (Art. 3 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, Art.
6 [1] of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights).
-
This Declaration was incorporated by the UN General Assembly into its
resolution 3348 (XXIX) on 17 December 1974.
-
Concerning the definition of the concept of non-intervention in internal
affairs, cf. Tomislav Mitrović, "Non-intervention in the Internal
Affairs of States," in: Milan Sahović (ed.),
Principles of International
Law concerning Friendly Relations and Cooperation, Belgrade 1972, pp. 219-275.
-
"Nothing in the foregoing paragraphs shall be construed as affecting
the relevant provisions of the Charter relating to the maintenance of international
peace and security."
-
"Every State has the primary responsibility to promote the economic,
social and cultural development of its people."
-
Cf. United States Economic Measures Against Cuba. Proceedings in the
United Nations and International Law Issues. Introduction by Richard Falk.
Northampton/ Mass. 1993.
-
Cf. the essay by the author, Democracy and new World Order.
Studies in International Relations, XIX. International Progress Organization,
Vienna 1993.
-
"... there should definitely be a provision at least recognizing
that States could take economic measures pursuant to a Security Council
resolution under Article 41 of the Charter of the United Nations."
(Report of the Secretary-General, Economic Measures as a Means of Political
and Economic Coercion against Developing Countries, Doc. A/44/510, October
10, 1989: Report of the Expert Group Meeting, para. 22)
-
The Convention speaks in connection with the question of the termination
or suspension of treaties of "provisions relating to the protection
of the human person contained in treaties of a humanitarian character,
in particular to provisions prohibiting any form of reprisals against persons
protected by such treaties." (United Nations/ General Assembly, Doc.
A/CONF.39/27, 23 May 1969, p. 29.)
-
Cf. also Gowlland-Debbas, "Security Council Enforcement Action
and Issues of State Responsibility," op. cit., p. 93. She refers to
this provision of the Vienna Convention as restricting the validity of
Art. 103 of the UN Charter.
-
"The existence of widespread extreme poverty inhibits the full
and effective enjoyment of human rights ... " Cf. also the recommendation
of the NGO-Forum, All Human Rights for All, Report by the General Rapporteur,
12 June 1993, Working Group D, Recommendation n. 6: "The recognition
of impoverishment of large sectors of the population as a gross violation
of human rights civil, political, economic, social, cultural in their
entirety."
-
Human rights and unilateral coercive measures: Commission on Human Rights,
56th meeting, 4 March 1994, res. 1994/47.
-
The International Progress Organization, before the Commission on Human
Rights (Sub-commission on the Prevention of Discrimination and Protection
of Minorities) has already (on 13 August 1991) pointed out the violations
of human rights brought about by economic sanctions measures with reference
to the case of Iraq. The Sub-Commission has also appealed in its Resolutions
1990/109 and 1991/108 to those states participating in sanctions against
Iraq that they take into account the fundamental human rights of the Iraqi
civilian population and especially those of the children. Although the
Commission on Human Rights has not directed an appeal concerning this humanitarian
issue as demanded by the I.P.O. to the Security Council, it has nevertheless
reflected the I.P.O.'s humanitarian concern of intervention in the resolution
on unilateral coercive measures quoted earlier.
-
Concerning the current discussion about the instruments of international
humanitarian law, cf. Bulletin of Human Rights 91/1, I: "Human rights
and humanitarian law," United Nations, New York 1992.
-
Verdross/ Simma, Universelles Völkerrecht, p. 148,
§ 242.
-
Protocol Additional to the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and
Relating to the Protection of Victims of International Armed Conflicts
(Protocol I, signed on 10 June 1977), Art. 54: Protection of objects
indispensable
to the survival of the civilian population. Cf. also the identical formulation
in Art. 14 of the 2nd Additional Protocol (with reference to internal armed
conflicts). Humanitarian exceptions for comprehensive sanctions (with regard
to medical supplies and food) follow from Art. 23 of the 4th Geneva Convention:
Geneva Convention Relative to the Protection of Civilian Persons in Time
of War of August 12, 1949.
-
Cf. the editorial "Let Our People Live,"
The Arab Review (London),
vol. 2, n. 3, Winter 1994), pp.2-4. Cf. also "International Law Experts
Resolution," International Symposium on U.S. War Crimes and Embargo
Violations of Human Rights in Iraq, February 5-8, 1994. Baghdad 1994, pp.
12-15.
-
"It is prohibited to attack, destroy, remove or render useless
objects indispensable to the survival of the civilian population ..."
-
Art. 48, Basic Rule: "In order to ensure respect for and protection
of the civilian population and civilian objects, the Parties to the conflict
shall at all times distinguish between the civilian population and combatants
..."
-
"Appeal for Action to Prohibit All Embargoes against a Whole Nation,"
Contra los embargos y sanciones económicas, Dossier I, OSPAAAC,
Madrid [1994], p. 1.
-
For recent considerations of the precise and binding formulation of
the principles of humanitarian action, cf. L. Minear and T.
G. Weiss, Humanitarian
Action in Time of War. Boulder/ London 1993. Cf. also the "Providence
Principles of humanitarian action in armed conflicts" (Minear/ Weiss,
p. 19).
-
"les populations et les belligérants restent sous la sauvegarde
et sous l'empire des principes du droit des gens, tels qu'ils résultent
des usages établis entre nations civilisées, des lois de
l'humanité et des exigences de la conscience publique." (Preamble
of the Convention concernant les lois et coutumes de la guerre sur terre
du 18 octobre 1907, quoted according to Die Haager Landkriegsordnung (Das
Übereinkommen über die Gesetze und Gebräuche des Landkrieges).
Textausgabe mit einer Einführung von Rudolf Laun. Wolfenbüttel-Hannover
[3rd ed.]1947, p. 68.
-
Protocol I (1977), Part I: General Provisions,
Art. I (2): "... civilians and combatants remain under the protection and authority of the
principles of international law derived from established custom, from the
principles of humanity and from the dictates of public conscience."
-
Cf. Gowlland-Debbas, "Security Council Enforcement Action and Issues
of State Responsibility," op. cit., particularly Chapter III: "Limits
to the Enforcement of the Security Council," pp. 90ff.
-
Cf. Bin Cheng, "General Principles of the Law in the Concept of
Responsibility, 7: The Principle of Individual Responsibility," in:
General Principles of Law as applied by International Courts and Tribunals.
London 1953, pp. 208ff.
-
"It must be said that the members of the U.N. Security Council
bear a ... moral and legal responsibility for the grave consequences of
the continuation of the sanctions..." (Commission on Human Rights,
Sub-Commission on Prevention of Discrimination and Protection of Minorities,
Forty-third session, 5-30 August 1991, Presentation by Warren A.
J. Hamerman,
International Progress Organization): Summary Record of the 10th meeting,
13 August 1991, Doc. E/CN.4/Sub.2/1991/SR.10/20 August 1991, para. 95,
p. 20).
-
Le pouvoir de sanction de l'O.N.U. Etude théorique de la coercition
non militaire. Paris 1974.
-
Op. cit., pp. 340ff.
-
Op. cit., p. 343.
-
Para. 41: "Sanctions and special economic problems," in:
An
Agenda for Peace. Preventive Diplomacy, Peacemaking and Peace-keeping.
Report of the Secretary-General pursuant to the statement adopted by the
Summit Meeting of the Security Council on 31 January 1992. United Nations,
New York 1992, p. 24.
-
Report of the Secretary-General on the Work of the Organization, United
Nations General Assembly/ Security Council, Doc. A/50/60, S/1995/1, 3 January
1995, esp. para. 70).
-
Die völkerrechtliche Verantwortlichkeit internationaler Organisationen
gegenüber Drittstaaten. Vienna/ New York 1969.
-
Op. cit., p. 181.
-
Ibid.
-
"In order to ensure prompt and effective action by the United Nations,
its Members confer on the Security Council primary responsibility for the
maintenance of international peace and security, and agree that in carrying
out its duties under this responsibility the Security Council acts on their
behalf." (Emphasis added by the author.)
-
Op. cit., p. 181.
-
Op. cit., pp. 181f.
-
Cf. the essay by the author, The Voting Procedure in the United
Nations Security Council. Examining a Normative Contradiction in the UN
Charter and its Consequences on International Relations. Studies in
International Relations, XVII. International Progress Organization, Vienna 1991.
-
Concerning the fundamental issues, cf. the reflections of Hans Kelsen
which preceded the conception of the Nürnberg Tribunal and of the
Genocide Convention: "Individual responsibility for acts of State,"
in: Peace through Law. Chapel Hill 1944, Part II: "Peace Guaranteed by Individual
Responsibility for Violations of International Law,"
pp. 81ff.
-
"A grave and systematic violation of human rights and fundamental
freedoms is carried out against the entire population of Iraq, in form
and dimensions without precedent ... That such a policy be carried out
on the basis of decisions made by a U.N. organ is unprecedented in the
history of the U.N. ... A further special feature of this case is that
the violation is being carried out not by a national government, but by
an intergovernmental body against the population of a member State of the
U.N." (para. 95, p. 20).
-
Originally formulated as "Charter of the International Military
Tribunal at Nürnberg" as part of the London Agreement for the
Prosecution and Punishment of the Major War Criminals of the European Axis
of August 19, 1945. It was then affirmed by a unanimous resolution of the
UN General Assembly: "Affirmation of the Principles of International
Law recognized by the Charter of the Nürnberg Tribunal" (resolution
95 [1] of 11 December, 1946). Cf. Alfons Klafkowski, Die Nürnberger
Prinzipien und die Entwicklung des Völkerrechts. Warsaw 1966.
-
Cf. particularly the complaint of the Commission of Inquiry for the
International War Crimes Tribunal in connection with the Gulf War. This
Commission explicitly lists "crimes against humanity" (Commission
of Inquiry for the International War Crimes Tribunal, Initial Complaint,
New York, 9 May 1991, p. 1). Cf. also the judgment of the International
War Crimes Tribunal of 29 February 1992, in which the continuation of sanctions
is described as a "crime against humanity".
-
Concerning this concept and its distinction from the concept of war
crimes in connection with the definitions of the Nürnberg Tribunal,
cf. John Fried, "Observations on the Concepts of War Crimes and Crimes
against Humanity," in: Toward a Right to Peace. Selected Papers of
John H.E. Fried with a foreword by Roger S. Clark. Northampton/Mass. 1994,
pp. 43-58.
-
Formulation of the Principles of International Law Recognized in the
Charter of the Nürnberg Tribunal and in the Judgment of the Tribunal:
Text of the Nürnberg Principles adopted by the International Law Commission
(44th to 49th meetings, 12 to 19 June 1950), United Nations/ General Assembly,
Doc. A/CN.4/L/2, 24 June 1950, p. 2.
-
Cf. particularly the report of the commission which he initiated, namely
the Commission of Inquiry for the International War Crimes Tribunal Initial Complaint of 9 May 1991. Cf. also his article in the
Los Angeles Times
(22 February 1994). Cf. also the statement by Third World Solidarity, "US
imposed sanctions and blockades on Third World countries" (London,
23 July 1994): "The sanctions policy is clearly a Crime against Humanity
as defined under the terms of the Nuremberg Principles." Cf. also
the editorial "Let Our People Live," op. cit., p. 3: "The
total blockade is morally indefensible ..." The editorial mentions
in this context the "rubber stamping Security Council claiming international
legitimacy for genocide."
-
International Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime
of Genocide (1948), Art. II, para. c.
-
Indictment, Complaint and Petition by the 4.5 million Children from
Iraq for Relief from Genocide by President Bush and the United States of
America [Sept. 18, 1991].
-
Yearbook of the International Law Commission 1980, Vol. II, Part Two:
Report of the Commission to the General Assembly on the work of its thirty-second
session. [Doc. A/35/10] New York 1981, Chapter III: State Responsibility,
p. 32.
-
Ibid.
-
In the rulings of the International Court of Justice, as well, this
specific legal obligation towards the community of states as a whole ("obligations erga omnes")
in contrast to the obligation merely towards single
states has been described. An obligation of this sort in current international
law according to the International Court of Justice results "from
the outlawing of acts of aggression, and of genocide, as also from the
principles and rules concerning the basic rights of the human person."
(Barcelona Traction, Light and Power Company, Limited, Judgement, I.C.J
Reports 1970, p.33.)
-
"The Demand for Equity and Equality: The North South Divide in
the United Nations," in: Hans Köchler (ed.), The United Nations
and International Democracy. Vienna 1995, pp. 17-36.
-
The current state of affairs is criticized in a recent report to the
Commission on Human Rights: "There are no criteria, developed by the
United Nations for guiding decision-making and choice in cases of conflict
between duties, functions, rights and values." (Claire Palley, Implications
of Humanitarian Activities for the Enjoyment of Human Rights, loc. cit., para. 16, p.7.)
-
According to Karl Joseph Partsch, "Von der Souveränität
zur Solidarität. Wandelt sich das Völkerrecht?" in: Europäische
Menschenrechtszeitschrift, vol. 18, n. 21-22, 1991, p. 475.
-
Cf. the attempt to formulate practical rules for humanitarian action,
"The Providence Principles of humanitarian action in armed conflicts,"
in: Larry Minear/ Thomas G. Weiss, op. cit., p. 19.
-
John Quigley has characterized this international rule of law as follows:
"If the brave new world of harmony is to emerge, the rule of law must
be central, both at the domestic and international levels. All people must
be secure in their person, well-being, and property, and all must be assured
a minimum level of food, health care, education and opportunity."
("Prospects for the International Rule of Law," Emory International
Law Review, vol. 5, n. 2 [Fall 1991], p. 320.)
-
The International Institute of Humanitarian Law explicitly formulates
a "Right to Humanitarian Assistance", which is derived from the
fundamental human rights. Cf. the statement of the Institute, Guiding Principles
on the Right to Humanitarian Assistance (April 1993).
-
Cf. Ramsey Clark's approach. He recommends an International Convention
Prohibiting Blockades and Penalizing Violators ("Appeal for action
to prohibit all embargoes against a whole nation," loc. cit., p. 3).
Cf. also his commentary, "Iraq Embargo is Killing Kids; End it Now"
(Los Angeles Times, 22 February 1994) in which he additionally demands
a convention to define economic oppression against a whole people as a
crime against humanity.
|