|
Hans Köchler Professor of Philosophy, University of Innsbruck, Austria Co-Chairman, International Academy for Philosophy (IAPh)
The Policy of Violence Report presented at the Scientific Forum organized in the framework of the Rapprochement and Human Harmony Week (3rd) organized by Sultan Qaboos Higher Center for Culture & Science Sultan Qaboos Grand Mosque Muscat, Oman, 4 February 2014 |
I.P.O. Online Publications International Progress Organization, A-1010 Vienna, Kohlmarkt 4, Austria © International Progress Organization, 2014 |
Contents
Abstract (I) Violence and state authority (II) Violence at the domestic level
(III) Violence at the international level
(IV)
Conclusion:
The exclusionary nature of violence versus the inclusive mandate of politics |
ABSTRACT
The legitimacy of a political system is essentially determined by its ability to restrict, and ultimately prevent, the exercise of violence in society on the basis of clearly defined legal rules and procedures, so as to ensure political stability and a dignified life for all citizens. Any political use of violence, whether by interest groups or state organs, must be prevented.
The use of
force by the state must be restricted to the prevention, or
containment, of violent acts domestically and to the repulsion of
violence (aggression) internationally.
Accordingly, under the rule of law, the only option is the legal use
of force as a measure of self-defense of the polity, and within the
checks and balances of the constitution.
A
deliberate “policy of violence” – that is based on the creation of
fear among the citizens – is not only incompatible with basic human
rights, but is diametrically opposed to the raison d’être of every
state.
At the same time, the state has the responsibility to provide
conditions of social justice and equality to all its citizens so as to
eliminate possible causes of violence. When it comes to a sustainable
policy of the avoidance of violence, justice and the rule of law are
the reverse side of the coin.
On the basis of these maxims, the paper (1) analyzes the nature and
scope of violence in the context of political philosophy and
contemporary international law. The paper describes the destructive
impact of violence on social cohesion and political order in general,
and deals with its delegitimizing effect at the national and
international level. After an assessment of the specific role and duty
of the state and its legal system, the paper (2) explains the social,
political and legal implications of violence at the national
level (especially in situations of civil war and domestic terrorism)
and (3) analyzes the international use of violence (between
states as well as against states by groups or individuals, as
in the cases of international terrorism). The interdependence between
domestic and international violence is particularly explored. The
paper (4) concludes with a reflection on the exclusionary nature and
effect of violence in contrast to the integrative mandate of the
state, and draws the political and legal consequences from a general
ban on the use of force for political aims.
(I)
Violence and state authority*
Civilization requires, first and foremost, the taming of violence.
Many philosophers have described the “state of nature” as the opposite
of civilization. In this primitive state, anarchy and lawlessness
prevail,[1]
conditions that make it impossible for a society to prosper, and which
prevent the advancement of humanity – in the individual as well as in
the collective sense.[2]
One of the decisive criteria or measures for a group’s (a
collective’s, a nation’s) civilizational status is the extent to which
it is able to control violent behavior of its members, but also of
itself as a collective actor (state) vis-à-vis other collectives
(states). The “basic lesson of civilization,” one might say, is that
of moral self-constraint in terms of social behavior. Unlike in the
state of nature, in the state of civilization, violence as a form of
social interaction is to be replaced, albeit realistically only in
gradual steps, by co-operation – a form of behavior that requires (a)
mutual respect and (b) the acceptance of general rules of behavior
that are derived from the principle of equality of all human beings.
It is against this background that the antagonism between law and
violence becomes a central issue of state identity. It is the special
role of the state, as organizational structure, to ensure the
suppression of violent behavior by its citizens, and to achieve this
goal on the basis of clearly defined legal norms. This is why the
state must possess the “monopoly of violence” (in the sense of a
monopoly of the legitimate use of force)[3]
– in order to preserve an order of non-violence and peace among its
citizens.[4]
The very essence of the rule of law lies in this authority of the
state at the meta-level, namely its power to “enforce” the
basic norm of non-violence on a consistent and sustainable basis. This
alone will enable the citizens of the state to live free of fear and,
thus, to fully develop their humanity; and this capability alone will
distinguish a state, as a legitimate legal entity, from a “failed
state” – where the state’s inability to control violence among groups
on its territory, its loss of the monopoly on violence, has led to a
situation of anarchy.
Reversely, the state, as the enforcer of the law, must not itself
engage in a policy of violence against its citizens. Force must only
be used in the interest of the common good, namely for the
preservation of the state’s legal order (including the norm of
non-violence), and within strict legal (constitutional) constraints.
This applies to the domestic, but also to the international level –
where the Preamble to the UN Charter clearly states “that armed force
shall not be used, save in the common interest.”[5]
Only a dictatorship would adopt violence as a state policy.
In order to analyze the phenomenon of violence properly, it is
essential to distinguish between violence as a symptom and
violence as a method (i.e. as a tool). The latter characterizes
the action of the state as enforcer of norms (which is its
constitutional role) – but also, in the case of authoritarian rule, as
oppressive power, while the former relates to a possible form of
reaction by an individual, a group, or a state, to an actual or
perceived injustice or objectionable behavior. In order to minimize
the inclination, or resort, to violent behavior as reaction to
perceived injustices, the creation of a just and equal society should
be the main priority for a state that is committed to the rule of law,
as it should also be the main concern for the international community
in regard to inter-state relations. At the domestic level, this
concern – in terms of the reactive aspect of violence – is echoed in
the words of the late Martin Luther King, Jr.: “A riot is the language
of the unheard.”[6]
In order to avoid misunderstandings in terms of the legal
implications, a brief conceptual clarification is in place. In
contemporary discourse, especially in international relations theory,
the terms “violence” and “force” are often used interchangeably.[7]
Semantically, “force” has a wider meaning that also includes, for
instance, the “force of arguments” in the sense of the “power” or
“strength” of a certain position.[8]
“Force,” thus, could be described, more generally, in the sense of the
exertion of power, which may, though not necessarily, include violent
means. The “force of the law,” however, is ultimately guaranteed by
violent means. The main distinction here is between arbitrary violence
as a method of fear and intimidation (as in a dictatorship or tyranny,
or through a tactic of terrorism[9])
and the use of violent means on the basis of specific legal
provisions, and within a system of checks and balances (i.e. under the
rule of law) as, for instance, in a democracy or in a constitutional
state.
The issue of the specific role of violence in the context of politics
gives rise to the intricate ethical question as to whether “the end
justifies the means” – and under which specific conditions.[10]
All through history, this has been one of the most challenging
questions of state legitimacy.
(II) Violence at the domestic level
At the national (domestic) level, the resort to violence has a long
and varied history – in different socio-economic contexts and within
different civilizations. In situations where (a) a state fails to
ensure fairness and justice to all its citizens, or (b) the state
structure collapses due to internal or external factors,[11]
or (c) under conditions of sectarianism where ethnic, religious, or
social groups have succeeded to put their interests above those of the
nation
[12: in all those situations
violence may be perceived by the protagonists as the only means (1) to
settle disputes (that would otherwise be dealt with through
negotiations and rational discourse), and, more generally, (2) to
preserve a group’s interests in an essentially anarchic struggle for
survival, without any consideration for the common good or the
integrity of the state as such.[13] There are three typical situations of political violence[14] – or violence as a “political language”[15] – in the domestic context (which, however, cannot be isolated from the transnational dimension[16]):
(A)
Civil war situations: Examples are: the confessional conflicts in 16th
and 17th century Europe; ethnic conflicts in the wake of
state collapse such as the violence on the territory of the former
Soviet Union or the former Yugoslavia during the 1990s; uprisings in
the Arab world since 2011, which have resulted from situations
characterized under (a) above, and, in some cases, have led to
confrontations described under (c). These conflicts often include acts
of ethnic cleansing and genocide.[17]
(B)
Domestic terrorism: This means the use of violence by individuals or
groups to achieve specific political goals (that may be related to
economic, cultural or religious issues or grievances). These uses of
violence are essentially aimed at creating fear among the civilian
population and/or directed at institutions that are identified with
the power and authority of the state.[18] (C) Violence used by the state as a means of terror (“state terrorism”) to impose and maintain an unjust order or to uphold totalitarian control over its citizens:[19] This extreme and arbitrary (illegal) use of violence by state organs is not to be confused with what would be tolerable as (legal) exercise of the “monopoly of violence,” including the use of armed force, by a legitimate state and within the constraints defined by law.[20] Media violence
Apart from these typical situations, or constellations, of the
political use of violence, there are two pervasive societal trends
that underlie, and reinforce, a “climate of violence” which is
detrimental to social cohesion and political stability, whether in the
short or in the long term. The latter seems to be the case with a kind
of mega-trend in the consumer societies of the modern industrialized
world: Violence has become a rather common ingredient of
entertainment. For essentially commercial reasons, the media industry
seems to have opted to engage in, and exploit, a “cult of violence”
that, in the meantime, has become a hallmark of modern pop culture.[21] This
is more than obvious in an ever larger number of movies, computer
games, Internet sites, etc. In a comprehensive and far-reaching
analysis and documentation, American scholar Nancy Signorielli bluntly
stated: “Although violence has always been a part of society and human
nature, at no other time in history have people of all ages and walks
of life been exposed to as many violent images and messages as they
are today.”[22]
It goes without saying that the heroization or glorification of
violence, or its exploitation for purposes of entertainment, goes
against the moral teachings of virtually all religions. Nonetheless,
the public does not in any way seem to be immune against the
persuasions of the industry.[23] Due to individual states’ – and the international community’s – proven inability (or lack of resolve?) to contain this trend, the consequences are indeed deep and serious. They are visible in what one might call the “brutalization” of social attitudes, especially in the field of youth culture. It should surprise non one if, in the long term, this kind of violent social culture will lead to the fragmentation of society (threatening the stability of the state and its legal order) and to a “politics of violence” where the resort to naked force is not anymore taboo (whether in individual or group behavior). In this regard, we also must not overlook the brutalizing effect of wars on society in general.[24] Electoral violence
The other pervasive trend, with short- as well as long-term effects,
is particularly dominant in the non-Western world (although it was
quite common in 20th century Europe before World War II). In many a
country, the “politics of violence” has become a characteristic
feature of electoral competition. Conflicts of interests and
ideological disputes are waged with violent means, whether by parties
or other societal groups, or by the executive power of the government
(police or military forces). The tactics of intimidation, including
the use of lethal force, are similar, in nature, to terrorist
violence. Campaigns that are supposed to be a (peaceful) competition
between political programs and ideas, to facilitate rational choice by
the populace, often degenerate into fierce fights that remind one of
the literal, not just metaphorical, meaning of the German word
Wahlkampf (“electoral battle”). One could mention here many recent
examples such as the violent confrontations, in connection with
elections and the competition between political parties, in
Afghanistan, Algeria,[25]
Iraq, Libya, South Asia (India, Pakistan, Bangladesh),[26]
Philippines, Côte d’Ivoire, Kenya,[27]
Zambia,[28]
etc. This kind of political violence was endemic in Europe in the
period between the two world wars (e. g. in Nazi Germany,[29]
among fascist movements in other European countries, in the Soviet
Union after the Bolshevik revolution, in the years of Stalinist
terror, etc.).[30]
In a commentary on the situation in Kenya (which has also brought
about the involvement of the International Criminal Court), Daniel
Branch notes a dangerous trend in domestic politics, which he
characterizes as the “normalization of violence.” This also applies to
the “politicization of violence” (i.e. the use of violence as an
instrument of politics) in the other countries mentioned here. In
Branch’s analysis of the events in Kenya, “violence
has become a well-established means by which power and authority […]
is contested in a variety of settings.”[31] In such a context – where violence increasingly replaces lawful means of political competition – the polity disintegrates and the state, having abandoned the “monopoly of violence,” gradually loses its legitimacy. The country risks becoming a “failed state” whose fate may affect, and destabilize, not only the neighbouring states, but even the wider region. This is the typical situation of anarchy which (1), directly, is the result of uncontrolled violence between groups of society and (2), indirectly, the consequence of the state’s loss of the monopoly of violence. Spill-over
effect of domestic violence The international dimension of domestic violence is particularly obvious in the socio-political dynamic of civil war. The combatants, representing rival groups in terms of ethnicity, religion or vested interests, will sooner or later, and almost unavoidably, (a) look for outside support, or (b) attract outside involvement (whether intended or not), or (c) try to “export” the conflict to neighboring countries (as a tactic of war). The developments triggered by the conflicts in Afghanistan, Iraq, Somalia, Syria, among others, are clear evidence of this risk. In 20th century history, the civil war in Spain was another example of the “transnational dynamic “of civil strife.[32] The repercussions of “internationalization” – in terms of the dynamic of an originally domestic conflict and the impact and scope of violence – are far-reaching and serious: (a) An increase in the intensity and duration of the conflict: Outside support, or the expectation of it, will make conflicting parties even more intransigent und less inclined to seek compromise with their adversaries.[33] This will not only be detrimental to a negotiated settlement, which is obvious, but it will also have a long-term negative impact on social cohesion and peace. (b) Regional destabilization: Due to the involvement of third parties in otherwise local disputes or tensions, the threat of terrorist acts in neighboring countries may increase. The interdependence between local and foreign conflict situations may well create the risk of a chain reaction at the regional level. Examples are the situation in and around Iraq and, more recently, in and around Syria. In our era of global interdependence, civil wars and other forms of violence at the domestic level, mutually reinforcing each other at the regional level, may also have worldwide repercussions. Domestic and international violence cannot anymore be seen in isolation.
(III)
Violence at the international level
In a general sense, international violence can be defined (a) as
violence by and between states (“war”) and (b) as
violence by non-state actors against states. Historically, it has been
one of the main concerns of international law to regulate, and tame,
the use of force between states.[34] War
and the violent settlement of disputes has nonetheless been one of the
main features of the history of mankind.
An analysis of violence and its impact on human rapprochement at the
international level will have to deal with the issue of war-proneness
of states and its structural (systemic) reasons. There are basically
two aspects, or criteria, of a state’s inclination to the external
(international) use of violence:
(a)
War-proneness of authoritarian states (that practice a “policy of
violence” domestically): Aggressive behavior vis-à-vis other states (externally)
to divert attention from internal problems (that result from
domestic oppression and the deep social frustrations caused by it) is
a historically proven pattern of behavior of authoritarian and
repressive régimes. Conversely, it is argued that democracies are also
more peaceful internationally. Following Rudolph J. Rummel and his
extensive statistics of state behavior,[35]
the advocates of the “democratic peace theory”[36]
have been trying to prove that there is indeed a negative correlation
between the democratic organization of a polity and its inclination to
aggressive behavior externally. It is further argued that democracies
do not engage in violent conflict with each other.[37]
(b) War-proneness of great powers (i. e. as a characteristic of power politics)[38], irrespective of whether the governmental system is “authoritarian” (repressive) or “democratic”: A case in point is the so-called “humanitarian interventions” of the post-Cold War era.[39] Under the influence and effective leadership of great powers, military operations that would otherwise be outlawed under modern international law have been repeatedly undertaken with the proclaimed aim of protecting the civilian population in situations of civil war. However, it is to be ascertained in each and every case whether the stated humanitarian motive (“responsibility to protect”) is more than a tool of legitimization of an agenda of power politics that would, in its own right, not justify the use of violent means.[40]
Historically, violent behavior of states was understood to be one of
the political options that belong to the exercise of state
sovereignty. The jus ad bellum (“right to war”) was considered a
natural prerogative of the sovereign ruler. A paradigm change in terms
of international law – and morality – occurred only rather recently
with the general ban on the use of force in the Briand-Kellogg Pact of
1928 and in Article 2(4) of the Charter of the United Nations (1945).[42]
In view of these developments, war cannot anymore be considered –
according to the famous dictum of von Clausewitz – as the
“continuation of politics by other means.”[43]
The ban on the use of force also includes the interdiction of the
threat of force since a threat, as intimidation of the other, is
itself of violent nature.[44]
Irrespective of the potential merits of a multilateral use of force
for strictly humanitarian purposes, one must be aware of the
demoralizing effect of unilateral uses of force on the international
community (such as the occupation of Palestinian territories in 1967,
the invasion of Afghanistan in 1979, or the invasion of Iraq in 2003,
to mention only a few). How should the community of states ever
be convinced, and prepared, to respect the general ban on the use of
force – the main requirement of sustainable peace – if the most
powerful states simply neglect that principle, putting the assertion
of their “national interests” above international law and morality;
and how should the citizens be convinced of the (moral as well
as legal) legitimacy of these undertakings?
Furthermore, resort to war (namely the unilateral use of force)
totally undermines and discredits the idea of international
solidarity, and it creates mistrust between the peoples. A violent
foreign policy that operates with ultimatums and threats of
intervention against other states makes a mockery of the United
Nations Charter’s principle of “sovereign equality” (Article 2[1]) and
precludes partnership between sovereign states. It further strengthens
prejudices and reinforces enemy stereotypes, conjuring up the very
“clash of civilizations” that has become a major concern since the end
of the Cold War.[45]
It is a well-established historical fact, rooted in the psychology of
collective behavior, that aggressive action of states against other
states not only leads to violent reactions by the targeted countries,
but also may trigger chain reactions of international violence such as
last century’s two world wars. The dictum “violence begets violence,”
famously used by Martin Luther King, Jr. in the era of race struggle
in the United States,[46]
is particularly pertinent in the transnational domain.
It is therefore no surprise that, in view of the systemic
repercussions and in the interest of a stable global order, the use of
violent means is only admissible as an exception, and in the service
of the common interest.[47]
This relates to (individual and collective) self-defense according to
Article 51 of the UN Charter and to measures “to maintain or restore
international peace and security” on the basis of Chapter VII of the
Charter. The underlying idea is that of collective security – in
distinction from the arbitrariness of unilateral action that has been
characteristic of traditional power politics.
Among the most pervasive forms of inter-state violence are the
occupation and/or annexation of foreign territory. It has indeed been
one of the most enduring causes of conflict since ancient times, and
not only since the era of colonialism. As outright negation of the
right to self-determination, which has been generally recognized since
the end of the colonial era, armed occupation has not only provoked
reactive violence (“liberation struggles”) on the part of subjugated
peoples, but also has challenged the very system of rules
(“international rule of law”) on which today’s global order is built.[48]
The
arrogance of power, which is typical of imperial (or, more precisely,
imperialist) rule, is also obvious in the ambition to reshape the
cultural and civilizational identity of entire nations in the image of
the conqueror (or the intervening power).[49]
A case in point is the policy of “régime change,” or the imposition of
a different political system, on another polity by military force
(instead of through diplomacy and persuasion or, gradually, through
economic co-operation). Such uses of force have often proven to breed
further resentment, and to destabilize the polity in question. They
have almost always ultimately been counterproductive – not to speak of
their legally dubious nature (even if undertaken in the framework of
“humanitarian intervention” or as actions based on the “responsibility
to protect”).[50]
Another systemic problem of the use of violence in today’s
international order is directly related to the tradition of imperial
rule in 19th century Europe, and to the emphasis on
national sovereignty in an exclusivist meaning (that, in a certain
sense, is also documented in the provisions of Chapter VII of the UN
Charter). The five “great powers” of 1945[51]
– all of whom have acquired nuclear capability – enjoy a special – one
might say excessive – privilege as “permanent members” of the United
Nations Security Council. Due to the veto provision of Article 27 of
the Charter, they are the only countries that effectively are in a
position to use force against other states (i. e. unilaterally)
without the fear of coercive measures against themselves.[52]
Shortly after the foundation of the world organization, the Austrian
legal philosopher Hans Kelsen has identified this as a major problem
of, or obstacle to, the international rule of law (the achievement of
which is absolutely essential for peaceful co-operation among member
states as equals): “The veto right of the permanent members of the
Security Council places them above the law of the United Nations,
establishes their legal hegemony over all the other Members, and thus
stamps the Organization with the mark of an autocratic regime.”[53]
It is not surprising that this privilege encouraged – or reinforced –
what nowadays is called a “policy of double standards” in matters of
international security and peace. It risks making the United Nations
system of collective security (that is based on the sovereign equality
of states)[54]
entirely dysfunctional – with the long-term erosion of the very
legitimacy of the United Nations Organization as a consequence. As
recent history has demonstrated, the veto has also effectively
undermined the general ban on the use of force, and indirectly
encouraged the use of violent means for political purposes – and not
only by the most powerful international actors. In our era of globalization, with the ever more complex interdependence between states with different social, cultural, economic and political systems, a militaristic foreign policy and the unilateral use of violence have not only brought about an increase of regional tensions and made the world less safe, but also have contributed to a global climate of confrontation with civilizational undertones.[55] International terrorism
The recent phenomenon of international terrorism cannot be seen in
isolation from the unilateral use of violence by states.
The
controversy around the “global war on terror” touches upon the very
essence of the use of violent means by state and non-state actors
alike. It relates to basic questions of the moral and legal
qualification of the use of force in the context of global power
relations.
Terrorism, as instrumentalization of violence for political purposes,
is an almost classical case of the maxim “the end justifies the
means,” which expresses a perennial dilemma of political and legal
philosophy also in the face of the state’s monopoly on violence.[56]
For the purpose of definition, we understand as “international
terrorism”:
trans-border and/or internationally organized and politically
motivated acts of violence against civilians or state institutions or
state representatives with the aim of (a) destabilizing or destroying
a state’s political order, or (b) realizing a particular group’s
political (social or national) aspirations – whether domestically or
in a larger regional or even global context. (The latter motivation is
specifically ideological and not merely related to social or economic
grievances.)[57]
In general, the modus operandi of terrorism is that of instilling
fear, and its logic is that of blackmail. There are no other acts of
violence that would be more incompatible with, or diametrically
opposed to, social harmony at the domestic and peaceful co-existence
at the international level. In the absence of a legally agreed
definition,[58] the
General Assembly of the United Nations has characterized terrorism as
“criminal acts intended or calculated to provoke a state of terror in
the general public, a group of persons or particular persons for
political reasons.”[59]
It is to be noted that an “operative” definition of terrorism includes
acts of non-state and state actors (“state terrorism”) alike.[60]
If we follow this definition, the notion “global war on terror” will
have to be clarified in the sense of a joint, not unilateral,
worldwide effort to eliminate the causes of terrorist acts and to
apprehend those responsible.[61]
Any analysis of the phenomenon of international terrorism is
superficial, and will not be conducive to the formulation of policy
options, if it does not also deal with violence as a symptom, which
means addressing the (ideological) motives and (social or economic)
causes of terrorist acts. To merely describe those acts of violence as
acts of pure evil, committed by evil people for the sake of evil,
means to refuse a causal analysis based on a rational assessment of
specific social, economic, cultural and historical factors. This form
of demonization of violence gives terrorism a quasi-metaphysical
dimension, which it does not possess under the conditions of real
politics.[62]
Terrorism, as a strategy, is targeting the state as such; it is
aiming at the very integrity of the polity (as community of citizens).
Terrorist violence is meant to break the bonds of solidarity between
the citizens and to undermine, and ultimately destroy, the confidence
the citizen has in the state as guarantor of public order and
individual freedom, and as embodiment of the rule of law.[63]
Accordingly, the tactics of terror are defined by unpredictable
and random violence. Terrorism, including a state policy of terror,[64]
may well contribute to, and be the cause of, state collapse (as
in the cases of Somalia or Libya) while it may also be a symptom
of a failed state. This duality of symptom and cause drastically
demonstrates the complexity of a phenomenon that threatens social
cohesion domestically (since it may lead to the fragmentation of
society into mutually suspicious groups)[65]
and undermines, in an international context, the confidence that is
indispensable for durable peace among nations.[66]
Terrorism expresses the logic of war in its purest and most extreme
form. The terrorist’s tactic to impose his will by brute force
precludes any form of a negotiated settlement of the dispute or
grievances that, whether justified or not, may be at stake in a given
constellation. One may thus say about the nature of terrorist violence
that it is not merely illegal, but intrinsically unethical, and that,
in many instances, it has the nature of collective punishment.
In the interest of the community of citizens it embodies, the state
nonetheless has to react to the terrorist challenge in a rational, not
vengeful, manner. In order to be able to address the grievances that
may have led to terrorist acts, the state has to analyze the causes of
violence in all their complexity.[67]
The maxim of political wisdom – in regard to the challenge of
terrorist violence – could be summarized as the need for:
“understanding terrorism also as a symptom, but not dealing merely
with the symptoms.” Security measures, as advanced and sophisticated
as they may be, can only be ad hoc steps that will have to be
complemented by a political approach and a long-term strategy of
“containment” in a comprehensive social, cultural and economic sense.
A policy that is oriented towards societal harmony, at the domestic
level, and informed by a co-operative attitude, at the international
level, is indeed the best antidote to terrorist violence. The effort
dubbed the “global war on terror” will be doomed to fail if the states
engaged in it refuse to identify and address the root causes, and if
the rationale of that “war” is just that of a more efficient and
sophisticated use of violent means (in comparison to those of the
terrorists).[68]
Dealing with the symptoms can never be a surrogate for a comprehensive
political strategy against terrorist violence.
(IV) Conclusion:
|